Friday, November 4, 2011

Moral Sense and the Narrator of Tom Jones--- JAMES J. LYNCH




Recent rhetorical studies of Tom Jones demonstrate convincingly
how Fielding urges us to participate in the novel by making us
conscious of our own readership. John Preston, Wolfgang Iser, and
others show that our response to Fielding's novel is "epistemological
rather than moral," that Fielding leaves gaps in the text which
encourage us to make inferences about moral actions and to revise
these inferences as more information is presented.' These studies,
JamesJ. Lynch is an Assistant Professor of English at Virginia Tech. His book,
Henry Fielding and the Heliodoran Novel, will be published by Fairleigh Dickinson
University Press next year.
'John Preston argues in The CreatedS elf(London: Heinemann, 1970) that Tom
Jones is a "structure of successive responses to the novel" whose effect is "epistemological
rather than moral" (p. 114). Wolfgang Iser argues in The Implied Reader
(Baltimore: John Hopkins Univ. Press, 1971) that Fielding's narrator stimulates
"a process of learning in the course of which one's own sense of judgment may
come under scrutiny" (p. 31). He describes two principal methods by which
Fielding leaves gaps in the text: "schematized views" (the same event viewed from
different aspects) and the "principle of contrast" (presenting characters such as
Sophia and Molly who embody contrasting moral values). Both techniques create
vacant spaces in the text that invite the reader "to enter into the proceedings in
such a way that he can construct their meaning" (p. 51).
Iser's and Preston's analyses of the internal rhetoric of Tom Jones take their
points of departure from Wayne C. Booth's TheR hetorico f Fiction( Chicago: Univ.
of Chicago Press, 1961). Booth examines the nature of Fielding's "telling" narrator
and concludes that there is no similarity between the story of Tom Jones and
the narrator's intrusive addresses in which, he notes, "there is no complication,
not even any sequence except for the gradually increasing familiarity and intimacy
leading to farewell" (pp. 216-17). For other studies on the narrative point of
view in Tom Jones see: John Ross Baker, "From Imitation to Rhetoric: The Chicago
Critics, Wayne C. Booth, and TomJ ones,"N ovel 6 (1973): 197-217; Michael
Bliss, "Fielding's Bill of Fare," ELH 3 (1963):236-43; David Goldknopf, "The
Failure of Plot in Tom Jones," Criticism 11 (1969):262-74; Thomas Lockwood,
MORAL SENSE IN TOM JONES
by and large, remove the stigma of moralizing that earlier critics
attached to Fielding's intrusive narrator. Yet while they remind us
that the meaning of Tom Jones is dynamic, not static - that it lies in
process not pronouncement-they concentrate on the internal
rhetoric of the novel and largely ignore the ways in which Fielding's
narrator trains our ethical judgments in his formal point of view.2
I shall argue that in the prefatory chapters to Books 6, 7, and 10,
Fielding's narrator sets up a debate between good-natured and
ill-natured readers that teaches us how to respond with sensibility
to the events in the novel. In the first of these, the narrator focuses
on benevolent love and defines a way of responding to instances of
such love that suggests a correspondence between Fielding's concept
of"good-nature" and the ethical theories of such "moral sense"
philosophers as Francis Hutcheson.3 In 7:1 and 10:1, the narrator
applies the ethical premises of his argument in 6:1 to literary criticism.
We are thus programmed as critics not only to follow the rules
which the narrator indites as the founder of a "new Province of
Writing" but also to place our critical response in the context of a
coherent ethical system. The effect of these intrusions, especially
since they come at moments in the novel when we are most apt to
doubt the hero's moral worth, is to train our sensibility-our
"Matter and Reflection in Tom Jones," ELH45, 2 (1978):226-35; Arthur Sherbo,
"The Narrator in Fielding's Novels," in his Studies in the Eighteenth-Century Novel
(East Lansing: Michigan State Univ. Press, 1969), pp. 1-34; Philip Stevick, "On
Fielding Talking," College Literature 1 (1974):19-33.
2Bernard Harrison in Henry Fielding's Tom Jones: The Novelist as Moral Philosopher
(Sussex: Sussex Univ. Press, 1975), studies the philosophical debate that Fielding
enacts in the novel and the connections between Fielding's ethics and that of
the philosophers of the period. He argues against the puritanical view that Fielding
has left unresolved the question of Tom's infidelity by showing that Fielding's
ethical argument is completed by the ending. Harrison sees Fielding as combining
goodness of heart and prudence. Tom reaches this state at the end because of
his generosity to Mrs. Miller, to Mr. Anderson, and finally to Blifil. For other
views on Fielding's ethical philosophy see: Martin C. Battestin, The Moral Basis of
Fielding's Art (Middletown: Wesleyan Univ. Press, 1959), pp. 52-84; Henry
Knight Miller, Essays on Fielding's Miscellanies (Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press,
1961), pp. 60-75; Morris Golden, Fielding's Moral Psychology (Amherst: Univ. of
Massachusetts Press, 1966), pp. 20-41.
3Henry Fielding, The History of Tom Jones. Ed. Fredson Bowers (Middletown:
Wesleyan Univ. Press, 1975). All further references to Tom Jones will be cited in
the text, by book and chapter numbers.
600
JAMES J. LYNCH
capacity to react sentimentally and yet be aware of the rational
limits of feeling.
It is primarily this capacity to accept the hero's sentimental goodness
that makes the ending of Tom Jones feel right. Despite the
romance hopes we are programmed to entertain early in the novel
about Tom's eventual marriage to Sophia, the mechanics of a
purely conventional romance plot do not and cannot make the
ending satisfactory. Like many a conventional hero, Tom actually
is better than he seems; indeed, many of his misfortunes result
from the malice of a conventional rival, Blifil, rather than from
Tom's own indiscretions. Yet before we can feel right about the conventional
happy ending, we must reconcile our instinctive tendency
to approve Tom's good-nature with our rational tendency to
condemn his actions. The prefatory essays to Books 6, 7, and 10
urge such a reconciliation. They prompt us to admire Tom's goodnature
and to scoff at hypothetical readers who do not feel as Fielding
urges us to do. But more importantly, they modify a purely
sentimental response by pointing out the pitfalls of both approving
and disapproving moral actions too hastily. In short, they urge a
circumspection at the mid-point of the novel when Tom himself is
least circumspect.
The prefatory chapter to Book 6 is the first to focus exclusively
on ethical matters. The previous five prefatory essays dealt primarily
with generic criticism: what this history is like and not like,
how it will be embellished, and how it will pass over incidents and
periods of time not germane to the story. In 6:1, after Tom has
grappled with contradictory feelings towards Sophia and Molly,
the narrator presents an ethical debate on love which, for the first
time in the novel, formally establishes the ethical difference
between good-natured and ill-natured readers. Just as the plot
reaches a turning point in Book 6 with Allworthy's ill-founded condemnation
of the hero, so the prefatory chapters in the novel also
reach a turning point.
The chapter is cast as an essay on Love, but, in essence, it is a
debate in which the narrator refutes philosophers in the Hobbesian
and Mandevillean traditions who maintain that there is "no such
Passion in the human Breast" (p. 268). It begins with the narrator's
observation that those philosophers who deduce that "our best
Actions come from Pride" seek truth in the "nastiest of all Places, A
BAD MIND" (p. 269). He suggests it is as absurd for such philosophers
to find any "Ray of Divinity" or anything virtuous, good,
601
MORAL SENSE IN TOM JONES
lovely, or loving in their minds, as it is to find gold while cleaning a
latrine.
In order to avoid contention with these philosophers, he proposes
to settle the matter peaceably by conceding four points:
(1) that "many Minds . . . are entirely free from the
least Traces of such a Passion";
(2) that the word Love is often confused with Hunger;
(3) that, although Love "satisfies itself in a much more
delicate Manner," like Hunger, it "seek[s] its own Satisfaction";
(4) that, when Love "operates towards one of a different
Sex," the gratification it seeks is as strong as Hunger's.
(p. 270)
The concessions, as Bernard Harrison notes, characterize the philosophers'
position as "reductionist";4 that is, they equate the meaning
of the words Love and Hunger and thereby suggest that there is
no difference between the concepts to which they refer. Fielding's
strategy is to reduce this reduction to absurdity. He does so first by
proposing five counter-concessions by which he re-defines Love in
ethical terms:
(1) that "there is in some . . . human Breasts, a kind and
benevolent Disposition, which is gratified by contributing
to the Happiness of others";
(2) that there is delight in this gratification alone;
(3) that, if we do not call it Love, "we have no Name for
it";
(4) that this benevolent love "may be heightened and
sweetened by the Assistance of amorous Desires" but can
exist by itself;
(5) that "Esteem and Gratitude are the proper Motives"
for love; even if youth and beauty - the motives for desire -
cease, they have no effect on love.
(p. 270)
The definition Fielding asserts here, that Love is a "kind and
benevolent Disposition, which is gratified by contributing to the
Happiness of others," corresponds to the celebrated definition of
"good-nature" which Fielding sets forth in his Essay on the Knowledge
4Harrison, Henry Fielding's Tom Jones, pp. 59-62.
602
JAMES J. LYNCH
of the Characters of Men: "Good-nature is that benevolent and amiable
temper of mind, which disposes us to feel the misfortunes, and
enjoy the happiness of others; and, consequently, pushes us on to
promote the latter and prevent the former; and that without any
abstract contemplation on the beauty of virtue, and without the
allurements or terrors of religion."5
Love, like good-nature, is a feeling recognized by those who
have experienced its effects. It is selfless and transcends amorous
desires. As a result, it cannot be recognized by philosophers in the
Mandevillean and Hobbesian traditions who claim that man's
ethical actions are the result of pride. The narrator reduces to
absurdity the philosophers' claim that no such passion as love exists
by suggesting that they have based their conclusion on insufficient
empirical data. "Doth the Man," he questions, "who recognizes in
his own Heart no Traces of Avarice or Ambition, conclude therefore,
that there are no such Passions in Human Nature? Why will
we not modestly observe the same Rule in judging of the Good, as
well as the Evil of others?" (p. 271). Because the philosophers' reasoning
is confined to the jakes of their own minds, they are incapable
of distinguishing the sensation of love from the sensation of
hunger. They are, in short, incapable of a sentimental ethics.
In the last paragraph of the chapter, the narrator exhorts us to
accept his definition of benevolent love by appealing to our hearts,
not our heads:
Examine your Heart, my good Reader, and resolve
whether you believe these Matters with me. If you do, you
may now proceed to their Exemplification in the following
Pages: if you do not, you have, I assure you, already read
more than you have understood; and it would be wiser to
pursue your Business, or your Pleasures (such as they are)
than to throw away any more of your Time in reading what
you can neither taste nor comprehend.
(p. 271)
Like so many of Fielding's direct addresses to the readers, this one
implicitly urges us to adopt the pose of good-natured readers.
5Henry Fielding, The Complete Works of Henry Fielding. Ed. W. E. Henley, 16
vols. (London: William Heinemann, 1903; New York: Barnes and Noble, 1967),
14:285.
603
MORAL SENSE IN TOM JONES
What is more important here, however, is that the narrator defines
the kind of response he urges us to have by further reducing to
absurdity the incapacity of ill-natured readers and philosophers to
understand a concept which the rest of the novel will exemplify:
To treat of the Effects of Love to you, must be as absurd as to
discourse on Colours to a Man born blind; since possibly
your Idea of Love may be as absurd as that which we are
told such blind Man once entertained of the Colour Scarlet:
that Colour seemed to him to be very much like the Sound
of a Trumpet; and Love probably may, in your Opinion,
very greatly resemble a Dish of Soup, or a Sir-loin of
Roast-beef.
(pp. 271-72)
Fielding's analogy, drawn from Locke's Essay Concerning Human
Understanding, points out the central deficiency of ill-natured philosophers
and readers: they lack the capacity not only to understand
love as a form of benevolence, but also to respond affectively
to its moral qualities.
In its basic form, the kind of response Fielding implicitly urges
here is similar to what ethical philosophers such as Francis Hutcheson
call the "moral sense." I do not mean to suggest that Fielding
fully accepts Hutcheson's ethical theory; indeed, in later prefatory
essays, he refines the moral sense response urged in 6:1. Nevertheless,
Hutcheson's Illustration on the Moral Sense is useful for comparison
because in it he consciously sought to modify Locke's theory of
knowledge and to answer Hobbes's notion that man is innately selfish
and Mandeville's notion that morality and virtue are social contrivances.
Hutcheson argues that there is in human nature a
genuine motive for benevolence, that it is separate from self-love,
that we have a moral sense - or a tendency to approve certain kinds
of moral actions-and that the object of this moral sense is benevolence.
Other philosophers such as Hume and Butler theorize that
self-love plays a more direct role in our approval of moral goodness;
they explain the nature and operation of the moral sense in
terms different from Hutcheson's. What concerns us for this discussion,
however, is not the debate that took place among these
philosophers, but their common belief in an ethical faculty like
604
JAMES J. LYNCH
the moral sense.6
Hutcheson holds that every simple idea requires a sense, and
that the "moral sense" is the faculty by which we perceive and process
benevolent ideas. Analogous to the external senses, it is separate
and distinct from reason - even though reason corrects disorders
in that faculty, just as it corrects disorders in the sensory
faculties. The central question in Hutcheson's ethical view is which
qualities in human motivation prompt our approval or disapproval
of moral actions. The motive cannot be simply self-love, as Hobbes
would suggest, because self-love cannot account for "friendship,
gratitude, natural affection, generosity, public spirit, compassion,"
nor can it account for our approval of things done in distant ages.7
Hutcheson offers, instead, a counterview:
that we have not only self-love, but benevolent affections
also towards others, in various degrees, making us desire
their happiness as an ultimate end without any view to private
happiness; that we have a moral sense or determination
of our mind to approve every kind affection either in
ourselves or others and all publicly useful actions which we
imagine flow from such affection, without our having a
6Henry Knight Miller notes that Fielding's "moral creed" generally follows the
line of such latitudinarian preachers as Tillotson, Barrow, Burnet, and Hoadley,
but that their ideas had become so widely disseminated that it is not possible to
trace Fielding's creed to any specific sources (pp. 66-67). R. S. Crane examines
the connection between the latitudinarian moralists and the sentimental tradition
in his seminal article, "Suggestions Toward the Genealogy of the 'Man of
Feeling,"' ELH 3 (1934):205-30. Battestin examines many of these same in his
discussion of Joseph Andrews (pp. 14-25).
Miller notes that Fielding "agrees . . in almost no important regard" with
Hutcheson, "whose ethics of feeling is nearly as rigorous and rationalistic as the
scheme of Clarke and his followers" (p. 69). J. L. Mackie, in Hume's Moral Theory
(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980), offers a rather different interpretation
of Hutcheson. He notes that Hutcheson's use of the term "moral sense" has a
dangerous ambiguity. It may suggest an objectivist, almost a Platonic view: that
there is necessarily attached to benevolence some quality that demands moral
approval. He argues, however, that Hutcheson's moral sense is more subjectivist:
that our moral approval is "immediate, non-inferential, non-willed, and almost
universal among men" (p. 34). David Hume, he argues, follows essentially in this
subjectivist, sentimentalist tradition, while Joseph Butler gives the moral sense
an objectivist interpretation (p. 36).
7Francis Hutcheson, Illustrations on the Moral Sense. Ed. Bernard Peach (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 1971), p. 117-18.
605
MORAL SENSE IN TOM JONES
view to our private happiness in our approbation of these
actions.
(pp. 118-19)
This disposition to approve every "kind affection" exists outside of
reason, as it does in Fielding's definition of"good-nature." Indeed,
Hutcheson argues that it is not guided by choice: "We do not choose
to approve because approbation is pleasant, otherwise we would
always approve, and never condemn any actions" (p. 140). Rather,
approbation is "a perception arising without previous volition, or
choice of it, because of any concomitant pleasure. The occasion of
it is the perception of benevolent affections in ourselves, or the discovering
the like in others, even when we are incapable of any
action or election" (p. 140).
It is easy to see how Hutcheson's theory of the moral sense corresponds
both to Fielding's definition of benevolent love and to the
good-natured readers' spontaneous understanding of that kind of
love in his Heart. It is not subject to reason or to the "allurements or
terrors of religion," nor is it simply an instance of self-gratification.
Benevolent love, according to Fielding, may be "heightened and
sweetened by amorous Desires," but when age or sickness impairs
the sensual pleasures of love, the disposition to love benevolently is
not impaired.
By exhorting good-natured readers in 6:1 to accept in their
hearts the notion of benevolent love and to await its exemplification
later in the novel, Fielding implies that something like the moral
sense operates naturally within us. Yet, by presenting the illnatured
reader's deficiencies as well, Fielding implies that we must
respond critically as well as sentimentally. We must examine our
Heads as well as our Hearts. If Tom Jones were a different kind of
novel, and if Fielding's didactic purpose were simpler, an unrefined
sentimental response alone would suffice. However, since Tom has
already demonstrated a very human confusion of love and hunger,
we must concede the possibility that the ill-natured philosophers'
theory may, indeed, be an accurate way of describing Tom's
actions. Fielding's narrative point of view at this juncture thus
promises a sentimental ending, but also promises no easy means of
producing that ending. In effect, the narrative point of view creates
a kind of rhetorical suspense that anticipates the narrative suspense
of the plot.
The love defined in the prefatory chapter to Book 6, for example,
606
JAMES J. LYNCH
anticipates the sentimentalism implicit in Tom's letter to Sophia
later in the book, after the two are separated: "Believe me, I would
not hint all my Sufferings to you, if I imagined they could possibly
escape your Ears. I know the Goodness and Tenderness of your
Heart, and would avoid giving you any of those Pains which you
always feel for the Miserable. O let nothing which you shall hear of
my hard Fortune cause a Moment's Concern; for after the Loss of
you, every thing is to me a Trifle" (p. 313). Tom's moral sense here
is highly complex; he is sensitive to Sophia's sensitivity to his feelings.
The moral sense Fielding urges us to adopt thus helps us to
understand one part of the novel's suspense, the complications
affecting two sentimentally attuned lovers. For the sentimental
ending to work, however, Fielding must also provide a means by
which we can understand Tom's anti-sentimental behaviorbehavior
that confirms the worst expectations of ill-natured
readers.
Fielding creates such an understanding in the prefatory essays to
Books 7 and 10 by urging us to adopt an ethical perspective in our
roles as critics. He urges us to suspend judgments about characters
until we fully understand their ethical complexity. Importantly
enough, our circumspect pose is most fully defined at the midpoint
of the novel, when the hero, having succumbed to a certain
quantity of Mrs. Waters's amorous flesh, seems to have abandoned
love for hunger. From that point of the novel onwards, Tom's
behavior falls roughly into two independent categories: (1) action
that results from his pursuit of Sophia, including his affair with
Lady Bellaston; and (2) purely benevolent action, resulting from
his own good-nature, including his charity to the highwayman and
his intervention on Nancy Miller's behalf. The former category
ultimately leads to the seemingly insurmountable obstacles Tom
faces in the Gatehouse prison in Books 17 and 18. The latter category
ultimately provides enough evidence of Tom's good-nature to
redeem the hero in Mrs. Miller's eyes, if not in the eyes of Squire
Allworthy, Sophia, or the reader. In short, the qualifications the
narrator places on our critical judgments in 7:1 and 10:1 prepare
us for a proper weighing of these two categories of action against
one another.
In 7:1 - "A Comparison between the World and the Stage" - the
narrator uses an analogy between human life and the stage to
define the complex ways in which readers of the novel respond ethically
to events in it. At first, the intentions of the analogy seem
607
MORAL SENSE IN TOM JONES
merely to expose the various ways spectators respond to instances
of villainy and once again to separate good-natured readers from
ill-natured ones. As the narrator embellishes the analogy, however,
it becomes clear that for the good-natured reader to respond as
Fielding urges, he must become a privileged, behind-the-scenes
companion of the author, who sees not only the reactions of the
spectators, but also the various contradictory roles which individual
actors assume.
For the theater-goers, the process of arriving at judgments is
fairly simple. Those in the upper gallery condemn George's action
with "every Term of scurrilous Reproach" (p. 326); those in the
middle gallery respond in the same way, although with less "Noise
and Scurrility." In the Pit, opinion is divided: those "who delight in
heroic Virtue and perfect Character" object to an instance of
unpunished villainy, while the author's friends defend the action as
natural. All the "young Critics of the Age," however, call it "low." In
the Boxes, those few who bother to watch at all declare, almost
without the power to discriminate, that George was a "bad Kind of
Man," while those otherwise more politely occupied refuse "to give
their Opinion till they had heard that of the best Judges" (p. 326).
This survey of reactions, significantly enough, leads to no outright
correct view. Even the author's friends, who defend the creation
of villainy as natural, are not given prominence; their
objections are drowned out by the critics' cry of "low." What is at
issue is the very process of making judgments. In order to understand
the action, then, we must pass behind the scenes of "this great
Theatre of Nature" and circumspectly view the actors and the roles
they play. From this privileged position, we can "censure the
Action, without conceiving any absolute Detestation of the Person,
whom perhaps Nature may not have designed to act an ill Part in all
her Dramas" (p. 327). Once we are, metaphorically, behind the
scenes, the narrator urges us to see the "capricious Behaviour of the
Passions": the Managers and Directors of the theater. Since
Reason-the Patentee-is a "very idle Fellow, and seldom to exert
himself" (p. 328), the Passions "often force Men upon Parts, without
consulting their Judgement, and sometimes without regard to
their Talents" (p. 329). A man may thus act the role of a villain and
yet condemn his very own actions. Indeed, if Reason would intervene,
his Passions might even direct him to play other, more suitable
parts.
The ethical question Fielding raises, of course, has very little to
608
JAMES J. LYNCH
do with our response to Black George, for his predominant passion,
greed, remains fairly constant throughout, and his role is virtually
type-cast. But forJones, who is both splendidly wicked and
sentimentally heroic, the question is apropos: do we censure a bad
action without "conceiving any absolute Detestation of the Person"?
To put the question in terms of the conflicts developing in the
novel, do we condemn Tom because at times he is directed by Lust
not Love? The ending of the novel suggests that the answer must be
"No," but to be fully satisfied, Fielding implies that we must struggle
with the question itself: "the Man of Candour, and of true
Understanding, is never hasty to condemn. He can censure an
Imperfection, or even a Vice, without Rage against the guilty
Party" (p. 329). Wisdom comes from an ability to suspend judgment
about the agent of an action until we are certain whether it is
the agent himself or a Passion uncontrolled by Reason that is
responsible for the action.
Just as the narrator in 6:1 urges us to accept the definition of
good-natured love and also to recognize how ill-natured philosophers
reduce that definition to absurdity, so here we are urged to
suspend judgment and still recognize how quickly and for what
insufficient reasons others judge hastily: "The worst of Men generally
have the Words Rogue and Villain most in their Mouths, as the
lowest of all Wretches are aptest to cry out low in the Pit" (p. 329). It
is important that we recognize both sides of the argument because
the pleasure we take in Tom's eventual redemption comes, at least
in part, from thwarting the ill-natured critics' probable assumption
that Jones was born to be hanged.
The suspension of judgment Fielding urges here suggests the
kind of corrective system that Hutcheson builds into his theory of
the moral sense. In refuting the notion that reason must teach us
antecedently what is right or wrong before the moral sense can
operate, Hutcheson considers the possibility that our moral sense
might "approve what is vicious, and disapprove virtue, as a sickly
palate may dislike food, or a vitiated sense misrepresent colours or
dimensions" (p. 163). He solves the problem by asserting that reason
does not denominate objects perceived by the sense faculty
when they are in disorder, but "according to our ordinary perceptions,
or those of others in good health" (p. 164). Hutcheson is not
willing to argue that the exact same thing happens with reason and
the moral sense, but he suggests that such might be the case. The
implication of Fielding's analogy is that the Man of Candour
609
MORAL SENSE IN TOM JONES
should see more than idle Reason does and should not hastily condemn
a character who plays the role of a villain because the Passions
may force him to play a role that Reason-the
license-holder-may be too idle to correct.
The ethical position Fielding's narrator argues us into by 7:1 is to
accept the possibility that a character might act contrary to his own
good judgment and that we might condemn that action in itself but
not therefore condemn the actor. In 10:1 Fielding applies this ethical
position to the realm of literary criticism. Initially, the chapter
seems to be another in the series of attacks on critics, such as will
later be the topic of 11:1, "A Crust for the Critics." However, when
we consider the ethical questions he raises by the end of the chapter,
we realize that his strategy is not to attack ill-natured criticism
itself but to urge a way of seeing that corrects potential misreadings
both by good-natured and ill-natured readers.
The chapter begins with the narrator's usual separation of readers
into good-natured and ill-natured camps. The good-natured
readers may be as wise as Shakespeare himself; the ill-natured
readers, no wiser than Shakespeare's editors. For the latter group,
he offers three admonitions, only the first two of which apply to our
earlier sense of ill-natured criticism: (1) do not think incidents in
the story are superfluous merely because you do not understand
the author's design; (2) do not assume that different characters,
"actuated by the same Folly or Vice," are exactly the same. These
two warnings, by and large, are consistent with the observations
the narrator made in 7:1. To understand the novel, we must, as it
were, go behind the scenes with the author and understand its
design.
The third admonition, however, moves us away from potential
misreading of the author's narrative design into the realm, of
ethics:
In the next Place, we must admonish thee, my worthy
Friend (for, perhaps, thy Heart may be better than thy
Head) not to condemn a Character as a bad one, because it
is not perfectly a good one. If thou dost delight in these
Models of Perfection, there are Books enow written to gratify
thy Taste; but as we have not, in the Course of our Conversation,
ever happened to meet with any such Person, we
610
JAMES J. LYNCH
have not chosen to introduce any such here.
(p. 526)
On the one hand, the advice seems intended for ill-natured critics
who, like the ill-natured readers of 6:1, should pursue their pleasures
elsewhere. On the other hand the critic is not, strictly speaking,
ill-natured; rather, he has a Heart that is better than his Head
and that causes him to leap to disapproval because of a character's
imperfection, not because of his utter villainy. He expects models
of perfection in Art where there are none in Nature, and, is thus no
better than the critic in 7:1 who fails to recognize that a "single bad
Act no more constitutes a Villain in Life, than a single bad Part on
the Stage" (p. 328).
Fielding argues both that the presentation of perfectly good and
perfectly evil characters misrepresents nature and that in our
moral response to characters drawn from nature, we should be cautious
at leaping to judgments drawn singularly from our moral
sense. If an author creates a character of "Angelic Perfection," a
reader contemplating that character "may be both concerned and
ashamed to see a Pattern of Excellence, in his Nature, which he
may reasonably despair of ever arriving at" (p. 527). Similarly, if an
author creates a character of "diabolical Depravity," a reader contemplating
him "may be no less affected with those uneasy Situations,
at seeing the Nature, of which he is a Partaker, degraded into
so odious and detestable a Creature." But if, on the other hand, an
author creates a character which mingles good and bad, we must
temper our approval of the former and our disapproval of the latter
with reason:
if there be enough of Goodness in a Character to engage the
Admiration and Affection of a well-disposed Mind, though
there should appear some of those little Blemishes, quas
humana parum cavit natura [which . . . human frailty has
failed to avert], they will raise our Compassion rather than
our Abhorrence. Indeed, nothing can be of more moral
Use than the Imperfections which are seen in Examples of
this Kind; since such form a Kind of Surprize, more apt to
affect and dwell upon our Minds, than the Faults of very
vicious and wicked Persons.
(p. 527)
611
MORAL SENSE IN TOM JONES
Fielding's strategy transcends the rhetorical device of separating
good- and ill-natured critics. It is an appeal to a reader outside of
the text: one whose perception of the action is guided, as it were, by
the narrative frame. Just as a frame directs a viewer's attention to
the scene portrayed and sets limits for the painting, without
impinging upon the picture itself, so Fielding's narrative commentaries
direct our perceptions and, to a certain degree, limit or qualify
how we see the action. The particular qualification
here-responding to a character by means of a "well-disposed"
mind-prompts us to accept the hero, imperfect and imprudent as
he is, because he has enough of goodness in him to engage our
"Admiration and Affection." We are thus logically and rhetorically
argued into seeing Tom's benevolent disposition of mind at a point
in the novel when all the narrative evidence suggests he is guided by
Hunger rather than Love.
Although I have isolated 5:1, 7:1, and 10:1 primarily to show
how Fielding establishes a pattern for our moral and emotional
response to the novel, these chapters also play an important part in
the literary-critical response Fielding elicits in the other prefatory
chapters. By way of conclusion, let me briefly show how the two
patterns converge.
By urging us in 10:1 to suspend judgment about a character's
imperfections, Fielding directly connects our moral sense response
with our critical response to the text. He implies that ill-natured
critics suffer from an impaired moral sense and that their impairments
prevent them from seeing the design of his novel. Significantly
enough, Fielding's attacks on critics begin to develop about
the same time as he establishes guidelines for our moral sense
response. In 5:1, for example, he presents his "rules" for introducing
the serious into his history, lest critics, who he contends are
really more like law clerks, "assume a Dictatorial power" and "give
Laws to those Authors, from whose Predecessors they originally
received them" (p. 210). In 111: - immediately after his advice not
to condemn characters for their imperfections-Fielding argues
that ill-natured critics are merely slanderers; they pry into a book's
character "with no other Design but to discover [its] Faults, and
publish them to the World" (p. 567). Indeed, like the theater critics
in 6:1, they frequently condemn works by the general defamation,
"low," without assigning any particular faults and sometimes without
having read the work.
Fielding continues his attack on the malice and ill-humor of crit-
612
JAMES J. LYNCH
ics in subsequent prefatory essays, yet the principal aim of this
strategy is to refine our capacity to make good-natured critical, as
well as moral, judgments. He achieves this end in other prefatory
chapters in two ways.
First, he defines the qualities he himself deems necessary for a
good historian, thus inviting us to share in them, just as we are
invited to examine our good-natured hearts in 6:1. In 9:1 he
defines three of these qualities: Genius, Learning, and a good
Heart; that is, the ability to make rational discernments, the
rational collection of knowledge about human nature from books
and experience, and the ability to feel. This same combination of
the rational and the sentimental later influences Fielding's invocation
in 13: 1 . Here asking personifications of these same qualities to
inspire his work, he calls upon "Humanity" to bring with it "tender
Sensations" from which proceed "the noble, disinterested Friendship,
the melting Love, the generous Sentiment, the ardent Gratitude,
the soft Compassion, the candid Opinion, and all those
strong Energies of a good Mind, which fill the moistened Eyes with
Tears, the glowing Cheeks with Blood, and swell the Heart with
Tides of Grief, Joy, and Benevolence" (p. 687).
Second, Fielding calls our attention to potential ways of misreading
and misjudging his history, even without being illnatured.
In 8:1, a discussion of the literary uses of the marvelous,
Fielding notes that a writer must pay attention to probability and
possibility, particularly in "painting what is greatly good and amiable"
(p. 402). Readers will easily believe in "Knavery and Folly" he
tells us, because "Ill-nature adds a great Support and Strength to
Faith," yet a reader might easily think incredible a portrayal of pure
goodness. He demonstrates this fact by relating first the history of
a cold-blooded murderer, Henry Fisher, and then a sketch of
Ralph Allen's benevolence. The caution here amounts virtually to
the same thing as his explanation in 10:1 that an imperfectly good
character is more likely to affect our sensibilities than a character of
"Angelic Perfection."
In the same essay, Fielding also notes that a writer might be
tempted to violate the rules of probability by allowing a character
to behave inconsistently just to draw his work to a conclusion.
"Modern Authors of Comedy" almost universally violate probability
in this way, he argues, when they present heroes who are
"notorious Rogues" and heroines who are "abandoned Jades" in
the first four acts and then allow them to become, in the fifth act,
613
MORAL SENSE IN TOM JONES
"very worthy Gentlemen" and "Women of Virtue and Discretion"
(p. 406). His caution applies to the history he is writing and to our
response to it. A happy ending for Tom Jones might violate consistency
under two conditions: if Fielding made him into a character
of angelic perfection in the final books, or if Fielding failed to make
Tom's goodness of heart convincing. The moral sense response we
are urged to adopt prevents the former and adds conviction to the
latter.
Notably, the two cautions Fielding presents in 8:1 bear directly
on our response to events in the last half of the novel. While the
ill-natured critic in us tends to distrust instances of Tom's benevolent
goodness, the unrefined sentimentalist in us wishes for a
happy ending, despite Tom's behavior.
Fielding dramatically brings these impulses together in the
penultimate prefatory chapter. With Jones at the brink of despair
in the Gatehouse prison, Fielding pauses to tease the reader about
the probable conclusion of the novel. Despite his avowed "Affection"
for Jones and despite, perhaps, our willingness to accept an
improbable romance conclusion, Fielding insists that he will "do no
Violence to the Truth and Dignity of History" for the hero's sake (p.
876). He would rather confirm the worst suspicions of illnatured
readers and let Tom be hanged at Tyburn than forfeit his
"Integrity" or "shock the Faith of our Reader."
The strategy is to create suspense, but it is suspense, importantly
enough, about his allegiance to truth even at the risk of losing a
good-natured ending. We are thus left at this juncture with the
very uncertainty Fielding builds into our moral sense response to
the novel. We are torn between our intangible, intuitive feelings
about Tom's good heart and our rational inclination to condemn
him for his infidelity. Since Tom is not a character of angelic perfection,
the only way for Fielding to make a happy ending probable is
to force us finally to weigh his goodness against his imperfections.
The balance is clearly tipped in Tom's favor by Mrs. Miller's testimony
about Tom's good heart and by the exposure of Blifil as a
villain. Yet Fielding maintains the suspense even up to the penultimate
chapter, where Tom and Sophia are at last reunited. The
happy ending occurs only when Sophia is able to recognize, as we
have been urged to do from 10:1 onward, that there is enough
goodness in Tom's character, despite his infidelity, to raise her compassion
rather than her abhorrence.
614

Verbal Irony in Tom Jones Author(s): Eleanor N. Hutchens




VERBAL IRONY IN TOM JONES
BY ELEANOR N. HUTCHENS
W ITHOUT its verbal irony, Tom Jones
would be quite a different book: massive
and well made but lacking the high polish and
the effect of urbane control which do much to
preserve it as a major classic. Its realism, its
satire, and even its much-praised plot keep their
unified brilliance through being governed by an
ironic style that forms as important a contribution
to the English novel as any Fielding made.
A variety of sources beginning with Lucian
can be cited for Fielding's uses of irony. The
Scriblerus group were his acknowledged masters
in his own time, and French prose romance was
not without its influence.' But Fielding, in Tom
Jones, was the first English novelist who employed
verbal irony to hold a huge body of realistic
material, including a straightforward narrative
and a set of believable characters commanding
the sympathetic interest of the reader, under
the dual scrutiny of comedy and morality. As an
ironist he is generally held inferior to Swift in
subtlety, intellectuality, and force. But Swift
creates an abstract world-the nonexistent lands
visited by Gulliver, the weird mind of the
Modest Proposer, etc.-into which he draws
selected materials from the real world for ironic
treatment. Fielding treats people, events, and
ideas in their native settings, amid the mitigations
and qualifying circumstances that blunt
the edge of any but the most skillfully applied
irony.
That his verbal irony is best exemplified in
Tom Jones may be questioned by readers who
think of Jonathan Wild first in connection with it.
But the irony in Jonathan Wild has no basic
straightforward text to operate upon; the whole
text is ironic, like that of A Modest Proposal;
moreover, the irony is not so urbane and mature.
The long and greatly-admired passage on honor
(i, 13), besides owing much to Falstaff, has not
the subtle ease of a casually-dropped remark to
the same end in Tom Jones: "his lordship, who
was strictly a man of honour, and would by no
means have been guilty of an action which the
world in general would have condemned, began
to be much concerned for the advice which he
had taken" (xvIII, 11). There is verbal irony in
Joseph Andrews; but it does not prevail there,
and the style therefore has a more yielding surface;
Amelia too has it, but it is mired in the emotionalism
which renders the text boggy. Only in
46
Tom Jones does it achieve the triumphant
mastery that taught Fielding's successors.
Verbal irony takes several forms. As irony, it
is one of two main varieties-verbal and substantial-
of the sport of bringing about a conclusion
by indicating the opposite one. It is
effected by a choice or arrangement of words
which conveys the ironist's meaning by suggesting
its reverse. The suggestion clashes with the
context or with some view presumably shared by
author and reader (or at least known by the
reader to be held by the author), and the clash
comically invalidates the suggestion and thereby
strengthens the view with which it conflicts. The
forms of verbal irony are the ways in which the
suggestion may be made: by the denotation,
connotation, tone, or implied reference of the
words or of their arrangement. In Tom Jones
Fielding persistently employs all these forms.
Narration, description, characterization, and exposition
receive constant polish from them, and
to them the book may well be said to owe its enduring
brilliance.
Of the four, denotative irony is the simplest
and least subtle, consisting merely in the use of a
word to mean its literal opposite, as "noble" is
used in these passages:
[Mrs. Partridge] was . . . a professed follower of that
noble sect founded by Xantippe of old . . . (II, 3)
The great are deceived if they imagine they have appropriated
ambition and vanity to themselves. These
noble qualities flourish as notably in a country
church. .. as in the drawing-room.. . (iv, 7)
The noble bumtrap, blind and deaf to every circumstance
of distress, greatly rises above all the motives
to humanity, and into the hands of the gaoler resolves
to deliver his miserable prey. (vII, 3)
or as "good" is used in these:
'Every man must die some time or other,' answered
the good woman; 'it is no business of mine. I hope,
doctor, you would not have me hold him while you
bleed him' (viii, 3)
Amongo therg oodp rinciplesu ponw hicht his society
was founded,t herew as one very remarkable;. . . that
every member should, within the twenty-four hours,
1 On the French influence, see Wayne C. Booth, "The Self-
Conscious Narrator in Comic Fiction before Tristram
Shandy," PMLA, LXVII (1952), 163-185.
Eleanor N. Hutchens
tell at least one merry fib, which was to be propagated
by all the brethren and sisterhood. (xv, 3)
Denotative irony sounds a brief, sharp crack of
sarcastic humor, without those reverberative
qualities that carry the effect of other kinds of
verbal irony beyond the boundaries of the ironic
words themselves. When Squire Western's
demeanor as a magistrate is called wise, when
Partridge's remarks are called sage, when a
hideous chambermaid is called fair, the flat contradiction
of truth makes its brief impact and
dies, with no probing into relative validities (as
connotative irony is likely to probe) and no
transfiguring effect on the context.
Yet this is not to say that it has no part in the
larger effects of Tom Jones. These recurring snaps
of the whip have their function in helping to keep
the novel within its appointed bounds-that is,
within the pale of comedy and morality at once.
Take away "noble," take away "good" from the
passages cited, and in most cases Fielding's moral
comment is lost or dulled. Substitute "base"
or "bad," the straightforward truthful words,
and moral criticism is retained but the comedy is
lost. Where there is no moral criticism, as in the
case of the "fair" chambermaid, there is only
comedy to be lost; but the loss of one passage in
the novel from the comic view is a loss to the
whole effect. Denotative irony, then, although in
itself less interesting and stimulating than connotative
irony, is a useful auxiliary in the work of
producing the total impression of the novel as
well as in enhancing the liveliness of individual
passages. That Fielding himself felt it to be an
inferior device is suggested by the fact that in
Tom Jones he uses it sparingly, only about one
third as often as connotative irony.
This form, the one by which Fielding does
most to achieve the verbal brilliance of Tom
Jones, differs from the denotative in that the
ironic word retains its literal meaning but clashes
with truth in its connotations. I have attempted
to show, in another place, how connotative irony
is used to carry out one of the major themes of
the book;2 for present purposes, a demonstration
of its mechanics will perhaps suffice.
Fielding shows an analytical awareness of
connotative irony in the first chapter of Jonathan
Wild, where he takes pains to remove the connotation
of goodness from the word "greatness."
(Despite this explicit separation, the comic impact
of "great" as applied to Wild rests in its
connotative irony as we continue to associate
goodness, or worthiness, with greatness and are
therefore struck by a comical incongruity in the
application.) In Tom Jones, besides bearing
specific themes (the nature of prudence, honor,
etc.), connotative irony in its nature reflects
Fielding's governing comic-moral view that a
thing may be good or true in one sense but bad or
false in others. His use of "proper" illustrates this
point: "The captain was indeed as great a master
of the art of love as Ovid was formerly. He had
besides received proper hints from his brother,
which he failed not to improve to the best advantage"
(I, 10). The conspiracy of the Blifil
brothers is thus dignified with a word which,
while legitimately used to mean appropriate (to
the attainment of the end in view), carries connotations
of laudable conduct which are comically
inapplicable to the Blifil game. Squire
Western's indecorous behavior, Partridge's gluttony
and self-interest, and the rapacity of the
Man of the Hill's fellow gamblers receive similar
treatment:
The squire, however, sent after his sister the same
holloaw hicha ttendst he departureo f a hare,w hens he
is first started before the hounds. He was indeed a
great master of this kind of vociferation, and had a
holloa proper for most occasions in life. (vII, 3)
Partridge thought he had now a proper opportunity to
remind his friend of a matter which he seemed entirely
to have forgotten; what this was the reader will guess,
when we inform him that Jones had eaten nothing
more than one poached egg since he had left the
alehouse ... (xII, 13)
[Partridge]n o sooner discoveredt he principleso f his
fellow-travellerth an he thoughtp ropert o conceala nd
outwardly give up his own to the man on whom he
depended for the making his fortune . . . (vIII, 9)
'I mean... those gross cheats which are proper to
impose upon the raw and unexperienced.'. (vIII,
13)
In each case, an element of the literal meaning of
"proper" can be applied faithfully to the context.
The idea of fitness, in some form, is always
present; but the straightforward expression
would differ in each instance. "Cunningly aimed"
for Dr. Blifil's hints; "adapted" for the squire's
holloa (though even here there might be some
irony in the ideal of rational choice usually associated
with the word); all of the examples, which
range in subject matter from harmless eccentricity
through opportunism to actual criminality,
could have been rendered unironically in
terms not carrying the favorable connotations of
"proper."
2 " 'Prudence' in Tom Jones," PQ, xxxix, 4 (October
1960), 496-507.
47
Verbal Irony in "Tom Jones"
Usually the moral criticism is adverse, as in the
buying of Molly Seagrim's favors: "some wellchosen
presents from the philosopher so softened
and unguarded the girl's heart, that . . . Square
triumphed ..." (v, 5). "Softened" and "unguarded"
apply in some slight literal sense to
Molly's coming to terms, but the connotations
direct the reader to contrast her case with that of
the innocent victim of seduction. Sometimes, on
the other hand, the connotations are worse,
rather than better, than the subject warrants,
when Fielding wishes to excuse rather than to
blame: "This hare he had basely and barbarously
knocked on the head, against the laws of
the land, and no less against the laws of sportsmen"
(III, 10). Here Fielding shifts downward
into the view of the game-preserving squires, who
while they save the game from the hungry poor
"will most unmercifully slaughter whole horseloads
themselves" (III, 2). "Basely" and "barbarously"
do not lose all their literal meaning,
since the act is illegal and a violation of the rights
of property which, Fielding would have been the
last to deny, constitute a foundation stone of
civilized society; but the connotations of selfrighteousness
they carry, in their unwarrantable
severity, clash comically with the real moral position
of the squires. Thus Black George comes off
the better for them.
The technique of connotative irony is Fielding's
chief means of accomplishing the stylistic
effect of Tom Jones. Denotative, tonal, and
referential irony mesh with it, but they are not so
frequently used, are not so closely adapted to his
realistic materials, and all in all are not so well
calculated to give the whole its high polish.
Irony of tone stands somewhere between connotative
and denotative irony in subtlety and
staying power. One of the great life-giving excellences
of Fielding's prose is that in it we hear
continually the cadences, the modulations, the
pauses and accelerations of the human voice.3
Here, as elsewhere, his presence as author allows
him full play, permitting him a wide range of
tones not only in his own voice but in the voices
to which he shifts for ironic effect. (To deplore
Fielding's "intrusiveness" is to wish away his
verbal irony, which would be impossible without
it.) Tonal irony has little to do with the words
used; it does not depend on the raising or lowering
of diction, though one of these sometimes
accompanies it. It is achieved by the sequence in
which words are arranged, by the ordering of
clauses and phrases, and sometimes by punctuation.
When it does partially depend on the words
used, this dependence is owing to the fact that
those words demand a certain tone of voice when
they occur at a given point in the sentence. "Indeed,"
"at least," "never," "only," and many
other words and phrases in English take on
standard tones when they are placed in certain
relations with other parts of a given utterance.
... that surprising sect, who are honourably mentioned
by the late Dr. Swift as having, by the mere
force of genius alone, without the least assistance of
any kind of learning, or even reading, discovered that
profound and invaluable secret that there is no
God.... (vi, 1)
"Mere," "alone," "least," and other words in
this passage require, in the positions they occupy,
tones of wonder and admiration. These tones
clash, of course, with Fielding's real contempt,
ironically driving it home. In contrast to their
emphasis, here is a dependent clause which makes
its effect by virtue of its subordination:
It was Mr. Western's custom every afternoon, as
soon as he was drunk, to hear his daughter play on the
harpsichord .... (iv, 5)
The perfunctory, matter-of-fact tone demanded
by the "as soon as" clause is in comic conflict
with its meaning as statement and thus comments
ironically upon Squire Western's way of
life.
At its noisiest, as in Squire Western's sudden
irruptions into scenes of courtesy or sentiment,
the tonal irony of Tom Jones reaches the burlesque.
It is worth noting that in the "Homerican"
churchyard battle the tone, alternately
soaring and lurching like a schoolboy's translation,
participates in the effect as fully as do the
diction and the referential irony of classical
allusion:
Recount, O Muse, the names of those who fell on
this fatal day. First, Jemmy Tweedle felt on his
hinder head the direful bone. Him the pleasant banks
of sweetly-windedS tourh ad nourished,w hereh e first
learnt the vocal art, with which, wandering up and
down at wakes and fairs, he cheered the rural nymphs
and swains when upon the green they interweaved the
sprightly dance; while he himself stood fiddling and
jumping to his own music. How little now avails his
fiddle! He thumps the verdant floor with his carcass.
(iv, 8)
In its total range, irony of tone approaches
that of connotation as a contributor to the
persistent effect of authorial mastery that controls
the reader's impression of the novel. In ex-
8 Some readers seem not to have the inward ear with
which others hear whatever they silently read. To them,
what is here called tonal irony may appear to be purely a
matter of syntax or sentence structure.
48
Eleanor N. Hutchens
position it enables Fielding not only to create
variety by going beyond his own appointed range
of tones as straightforward lecturer but to introduce
points of view other than his own in such
ways that their possessors seem to be present and
exposing themselves to ridicule rather than being
exposed by him. Thus avoiding the appearance of
ill humor and narrow-mindedness, he seems to
be letting them have their say with perfect good
grace and leaving it to the reader to judge them.
In characterization it operates similarly as a
device for making speakers condemn themselves:
"No, no, friend, I shall never be bubbled out of
my religion in hopes only of keeping my place
under another government; for I should certainly
be no better, and very probably might be
worse" (xII, 7). Readers more sensitive to tone
than to substance are capable of taking this
speech as one of stout religious loyalty, so well
does the tone envelop the statement. The tone
of resolution created by the linking of "never"
with "religion" and the tone of deprecation in the
linking of "only" and "place" overwhelm the
sense of the final reflection, which thus subordinated
sounds as righteous as the rest while
actually marking the exciseman's motive as altogether
self-interested. Narrative and descriptive
passages likewise demand alertness to clashes between
tone and statement if the reader is to keep
up with the irony or even, in some cases, with the
action; for Fielding shows a perfect willingness
to couch important information in casual tones
that make it sound not only insignificant but
probably untrue: "In plain language, the only
way he could possibly find to account for the
possession of this note was by robbery; and, to
confess the truth, the reader, unless he should
suspect it was owing to the generosity of Lady
Bellaston, can hardly imagine any other" (xm,
8). We learn in the next paragraph that Lady
Bellaston is indeed the source of Tom's new
affluence, the slyness of the foregoing hint yielding
to a contrasting and equally ironic openness
and enthusiasm in regard to the giver's charitable
impulses.
Whereas tone, it must be acknowledged, is
sometimes elusive and often subject to question
because of differences in receptivity and ear
among readers, the irony of reference lends itself
rather more readily to objective discussion.
In its verbal form, it consists in the use of words
which by implication compare or refer a subject
to something else which in its comic dissimilarity
points up the real nature of the subject. Fielding's
customary use of this device calls in the
terminology of a body of learning-law, medicine,
classical literature, politics, science, or
military craft-to give the subject an air of
dignity, method, reason, or importance which
does not belong to it and thereby to emphasize its
lack of the quality suggested.
Tom was now mounted on the back of a footman,
and everything prepared for execution, when Mr. Allworthy,
entering the room, gave the criminal a reprieve
.... (iii, 8)
[Squares] oon found the meanso f mitigatingh er anger
... partly by a small nostrum from his purse, of
wonderfula nd approvede fficacyi n purgingo ff the ill
humours of the mind, and in restoring it to a good
temper. (v, 5)
An ancient heathen would perhaps have imputed this
disability to the god of drink, no less than to the god
of war; for, in reality, both the combatants had sacrificed
as well to the former deity as to the latter....
(IX, 6)
Now there was a certain office in the gift of Mr.
Fitzpatrick at that time vacant, namely, that of a
wife: for the lady who had lately filled that office had
resigned, or at least deserted her duty. Mr. Fitzpatrick
therefore, having thoroughly examined Mrs.
Waters on the road, found her extremely fit for the
place, which, on their arrival at Bath, he presently
conferred upon her, and she without any scruple
accepted. (xvII, 9)
In not every case, however, is the subject dignified:
the shift may be downward, as in Squire
Western's application of hunting terms to the
lovely Sophia-"We have got the dog fox, I warrant
the bitch is not far off" (x, 7), " . . . I'll unkennel
her..." (xv, 5)-and as in Fielding's
use, in his chapter headings, of the jargon of advertisers
and publishers of sentimental literature.
Here the irony operates in favor of the subject
by seeming to classify it in a clearly inferior
category.
Fielding's use of referential irony extends the
conceptions within which his material is considered,
relating his incidents and his characters
to greater matters or general ideas or established
institutions or bodies of thought; it is more than
metaphor in that its comparisons swell or
diminish their subjects in significant ways,
assisting in the continuous work of keeping them
under comic and moral surveillance. Thus it
makes a special contribution of its own in addition
to joining the other three forms of verbal
irony in the management of total effect.
Substantial irony is outside the scope of this
discussion, which seeks to show only how verbal
irony in Tom Jones operates in the creation of the
whole impression made by the novel. Let it
49
Verbal Irony in "Tom Jones"
nevertheless be noted that substantial irony
functions as a huge complement to the verbal
kind in unifying and holding together as living
tissue the materials of Tom Jones. The tripartite
structure of the book, so often credited with
giving it superior form and purposefulness, is as
naught beside the constant play of large and
small ironies of action and thought that keep
reaching backward and forward to draw its
multitudinous events and persons into relation
with one another under the comic-moral view.
Again, however, Tom Jones would be a vastly
different novel if its irony were substantial only.
Much of it would be grim, much sentimental.
(Take away the descriptions of Blifil as a prudent
youth, and the like, and the blackness of his
character would seriously darken the book; take
away the mock-reverential tones in which
Sophia is sometimes treated, and at points she
would dissolve into the sentimental heroine.)
However expert the writing, the whole thing
could not be carried off with the air of urbane
triumph that does in fact distinguish it.
AGNESS COTTC OLLEGE
Decatur, Ga.
"AND How DID GARRICKSP EAKt he soliloquy last night?"-"Oh,
against all rule, my lord. Most ungrammatically! Betwixt the substantive
and the adjective, which should agree together in number,
case, and gender, he made a breach thus-, stopping as if the point
wanted settling; and betwixt the nominative case, which your
lordship knows should govern the verb, he suspended his voice in
the epilogue a dozen times, three seconds and three-fifths by a stopwatch,
my lord, each time."-"Admirable grammarian! But in
suspending his voice, was the sense suspended likewise? Did no
expression of attitude or countenance fill up the chasm? Was the eye
silent? Did you narrowly look?"-"I looked only at the stopwatch,
my lord."-"Excellent observer!"--Laurence Sterne,
Tristram Shandy, Vol. In
50

Bulwer-Lytton and the Changed Ending of Great Expectations

. BULWER-LYTTON AND THE CHANGED ENDING OF Great Expectations WE DO NOT KNOW the specific reasons with which Bulwer-Lytton urged his view that the original, unhappy ending of Great Ex- pectations should be changed. We know only that Bulwer pre- sented "such good reasons'"1 and stated them "so well" that Dickens, as he says, "resumed the wheel" and took "another turn upon it." 2 Forster, who disliked the change, adds nothing either factual or conjectural about the reasons for it. With so little and such neutral evidence to go on, it is surprising that nearly every- one, even those recent critics who see merit in the second ending, should assume that the advice must have been crassly inspired. J. Hillis Miller, for instance, who makes the best case for the alteration, says that the advice came from "Mrs. Grundy in the 1. Letter to John Forster, 1 July 1861, The Letters of Charles Dichens, ed. Walter Dexter, Nonesuch Dickens ed., 3 vols. (Bloomsbury [London], 1938), 3:226. 2. Letter to Wilkie Collins, 23 June 1861, Letters 3:225.
Notes 105 mask of Bulwer-Lytton," 3 and Sylv&re Monod urges that in justice to Dickens we try to forget "that Bulwer originated the change." 4 Bulwer's arguments were presumably presented orally, and even if they were subsequently supported in writing, any letters would have been destroyed along with the rest of the correspond- ence Dickens received. However, from several of Bulwer's letters to other writers we can reconstruct at least the nature of the ad- vice, and I believe we can conclude that it was based on aesthetic principles which, however faulty they may be judged, should not be dismissed as either commercial or merely conventional. The general bent of Bulwer's practical criticism may be de- rived from a letter to W. E. Aytoun regarding the latter's Norman Sinclair, which concluded in Blackwood's in August 1861 simul- taneously with the last number of Great Expectations in All the Year Round. Bulwer writes: Perhaps if an old hand in the art might presume to offer suggestions, you might in future works of this kind find an advantage in deciding more resolutely between the questions of Plot and No Plot. I think that if, on the one hand, you discarded story altogether, and gave the freest swing to your powers of observation through one or two elaborated characters, like Sterne in "Tristram Shandy," or through playful philosophical monologue, like Le Maitre or T6pffer, you might make a delightful work of high character. On the other hand, if you resolved to seek interest in the movements of passion through the creatures and construction of fable, you might find it advisable to give your tale a more determinate backbone than there is in "Norman Sinclair." 5 This is elementary genre criticism based on "rules" which Bulwer had derived from his wide reading of fiction. In the final paragraph of the letter Bulwer is flexible enough to grant that Aytoun does "achieve an interest in defiance of rules," 6 but he had always been opposed to such unconscious license. As early as 1834 he had written to Lady Blessington: People often say to me "I shall write a novel." If I ask "On what rules?" they stare. They know of no rules. They write History, Epic, the Drama, 3. Charles Dickens: The World of His Novels (Cambridge, Mass., 1958), p. 278. 4. Dickens the Novelist (Norman, 1967), pp. 476-77. 5. & Jan. 1862; quoted in Theodore Martin, Memoir of William Edmondstoune Aytoun (Edinburgh/ London, 1867), pp. 217-18. 6. P. 218.
106 Nineteenth-Century Fiction Criticism by rules; and for the Novel, which comprises all four, they have no rules. No wonder that there is so much talent manqu6 in half the novels we read. In fact we ought to do as the sculptors do-gaze upon all the great masterpieces of our art till they sink into us, and we are penetrated by the secret of them.7 David Masson writes of Bulwer in 1859 that "of all British novelists, he seems to have worked most consciously on a theory of the Novel as a form of literature," 8 and a hundred years later Richard Stang calls him "the most articulate advocate" of the idealist position in prose fiction.9 The masterpieces on which Bulwer based his theories are those of Cervantes, Fenelon, Field- ing, Smollett, Le Sage, Apuleius, Sidney, and Goethe, writers of what he calls "narrative" as opposed to "dramatic" fiction.'0 From their works he derived his "rules," including the one which pertains to our problem of the ending of Great Expectations. In a letter justifying the questionable happy ending of his own novel, What Will He Do with It? (1858), he writes, "I hold it a principle in true art, because a vital element in durable popularity, which true art must always study, that the soul of a very long fiction should be pleasing." ll Translated into practical criticism for himself and other writers, this principle legislated, so Bulwer believed, that disagreeable or unpleasant elements have no place in a novel and especially in its ending. Thus he writes to Percy Fitzgerald around 1866 that he was "exceedingly struck by the depth and power of the earlier portions [of Fitzgerald's The Second M-rs. Tillotson], but with the later numbers I am not so well satisfied, and I believe the rea- son to be, not in any fault of mere construction, but because to- wards the close the antagonistic or disagreeable element over- powers the sympathetic or agreeable." 12 And in a letter written in 7. Quoted in The Life of Edward Bulwer, First Lord Lytton, by his Grandson, The Earl of Lytton, 2 vols. (London, 1913), 1:460-61. 8. British Novelists and Their Styles (Boston, 1875), p. 235. 9. The Theory of the Novel in England 1850-1870 (London, 1959), pp. 155-54. 10. This theory appears in a number of Bulwer's essays and prefaces, most fully in "On the Different Kinds of Prose Fiction, with Some Apology for the Fictions of the Author," in The Disowned (London, 1835), pp. vii-xxii. 11. Letter to John Blackwood, 25 Jan. 1858; quoted in "The Letters of Sir Edward Bulwer-Lytton to the Editors of Blackwood's Magazine, 1840-1873, in the National Library of Scotland," ed. Malcolm Orthell Usrey (Ph.D. diss., Texas Technical Coll., 1963), p. 178. 12. Quoted in Percy Fitzgerald, Recreations of a Literary Man, 2 vols. (London, 1882), 1:122-23.
Notes 107 1860 referring to The Mill on the Floss, he makes almost the same point. "In studying plot and incident-this very remarkable writer does not eno' weigh what is Agreeable or Disagreeable. Now the Disagreeable should be carefully avoided. You may have the pain- ful, the terrible, the horrible even; but the disagreeable should be shunned." He then lists several disagreeable elements in George Eliot's novel, including the ending, and, lest anyone suspect a com- mercial motivation in his advice, goes on to say: These are to my mind the same dass of defects as those in Ad. Bede, but they are not so marked, & those did not prevent or even injure the great popularity of Adam Bede. Neither will they, in this case; I even doubt whether they will be visible to most readers. -Where such de- fects really tell, (even supposing I am right which I may not be-) is 10 or 20 years hence in the duration of a work. They scarcely touch its first sale or the author's immediate reputation.'3 The stress Bulwer plaCes on "durable popularity" reflects his awareness of the recent change in author and reader acceptance of unhappy endings. Besides The Mill on the Floss, the last dozen years had produced Uncle Tom's Cabin, Hawthorne's romances, The Newcomes, The Ordeal of Richard Feverel, and of course A Tale of Two Cities. Bulwer obviously missed the aesthetic im- plications of this change but certainly not its commercial aspect, for he must have remembered that years before, when his literary theories were unformed, both he and Dickens had achieved great popular successes with unhappy conclusions. Bulwer's all- time best seller, Rienzi, had ended tragically, and the great heart- throb of English fiction before Little Nell had been provided by the death of Nadia in The Last Days of Pompeii. Clearly there was money to be made through tears. But while French fiction had not suffered financially from its long predilection for tragedy, the accepted classics of English fiction, which were Bulwer's chief points of reference, had traditionally ended happily. Exceptions like Clarissa and The Bride of Lammermoor had appeared so infrequently that they must have seemed confirmations of Bulwer's theory. Thus as regards Great Expectations Dickens was probably urged to forego what his friend considered a fashionable unhappy end- 13. See Usrey, pp. 233-34. The letter was addressed to John Blackwood with instruc- tions that it should be shown to the author.
108 Nineteenth-Century Fiction ing, designed to gain immediate popularity, and encouraged to substitute for it a conclusion more in keeping with what looked in 1861 like the time-tested rules of English narrative romance. Bulwer was fully aware that such advice was liable to the kind of misinterpretation it has received. In November 1861, only a few months after the talk with Dickens, he was forced to explain himself to his own son, to whom he had offered similar counsel. What Bentham makes his axiom in politics, helps to the axiom of poetic art. He says, "The greatest happiness of the greatest number should be the object of Govt." I say "the greatest delight of the greatest number" should be the object of poetic art. I add-which Bentham does not-for both-"and for the longest possible periods." Without that, both theorems are incomplete.... It is the greatest de- light of the poetic art for the moment to read Eugene Sue or Dumas. But we must look to the long run, and in the long run intellect pre- vails over numbers. The "popular" authors whom he recommended to his son, for study and emulation were Homer, Shakespeare, Goethe, Virgil, Horace, Milton, Byron, Goldsmith, and Dante.14 We are still free to question whether Bulwer was right in equating the happy ending with pleasure as an aesthetic criterion. But the validity of Bulwer's rules is not at issue in this note. I seek merely to point out that the currently accepted opinion of his advice to Dickens is unsupported by any evidence, and that the advice was fully consistent with Bulwer's criticism of other writers, with his own practice, and with long-considered theories, which he, and probably Dickens as well, regarded as literary prin- ciples rather than commercial practices. EDWIN M. EIGNER University of Kansas 14. Quoted in Life of Edward Bulwer, 2:397-99.

Great Expectations: "The Ghost of a Man's Own Father"
Author(s): Lawrence Jay Dessner

LAWRENCE JAY DESSNER
GreatE xpectations":t he ghost of a man's own father"
T HIS ESSAY attempts to provide a useful
account of Dickens' Great Expectations. It
makes use of some principles of Freudian
theory and of reports of contemporary psychoanalytic
medical practice. Psychoanalytically oriented
criticism of literature is, often, still an
enthusiast's cause. Pompous jargon, theorems
masquerading as axioms, repel us. Who has not
recoiled from a ludicrously farfetched Freudian
explication of a familiar text or from a speculative
psychological biography which reduces an author's
life to a sordid case history'? Forceful, even
convincing psychoanalytic explications feel different
from other forms of criticism: they do not
seem to spring from the conscious experience of
the reader-critic. They are not "proved upon our
pulses," nor do they correspond to the "Heart's
affections." And even the more circumspect
Freudians of literature are troubled by-and
trouble us with-the deterministic assumptions
of their theory. Proponents of human freedom
and dignity live uncomfortably with procedures
that imply conclusions such as this from Freud
himself: "The moment a man questions the
meaning and value of life he is sick, since objectively
neither has any existence."' Few of us envy
the role of patient, fewer that of guinea pig. Autopsy
without scientific or legal justification is
abhorrent. It may help, however, not to overstate
the parallel between the psychoanalyst and the
literary critic. The physician does not hope or
expect to enjoy his patient's narrative. Nor does
he listen in order to be morally enriched by sharing
the patient's emotional life. He seeks knowledge.
not experience oi pleasure. The work itself.
the patient's recitation, is no mor-e than a necessary
evil to him. an apparatus to be used and discarded.
Nor is the patient welcomed for his own
sake; the patient is somleone to be changed.
Great Expectations does not seem an especially
recalcitrant text, one with severe problems of
interpretation which might force us to take the
risks of the psychoanalytic approach. Traditional
criticism has prodalced a wealth of useful material.
We have been shown. for example. that the
novecl is "an extra chapter to IThe Book' o 'Snohs'"
an indictment of the social "condition of' England."
an allegory of the loss of Eden, and a
moral fable. "the story of a young man's development
fi'om the moment of his fiirst self-awareness.
to that of his mature acceptance of the human
condition."2 That such interpretations have generated
argument and denial need not impair their
partial usefulness. but none of the valuable lines
of approach we have is likel!I to prepare the
student, or the instructor, lori a passage like this
one:
The sun was striking in at the great windows of the
court, through the glittering drops of rain upon the
glass, and it made a broad shaft of light between the
two-and-thirtya nd the Judge, linking both together,
and perhapsr emindings ome amongt he audience,h ow
both were passing on, with absolute equality, to the
greater Judgment that knoweth all things and cannot
err. Rising for a moment, a distinct speck of face in this
way of light, the prisoner [Magwitch] said. "My Lord,
I have received my sentence of Death from the Almighty,
but I bow to yours," and sat down again.3
If Pip's struggles have brought him moral and
emotional maturity. if Dickens himself writes
fiom the vantage of such achieved maturity. this
passage (and it is not the novel's sole example) is
an anomaly. It is not simply that Magwitch and
his diction have leaped out of character. The narrator.
with his barrage of rhetorical maneuvers
and the contrivances of the visual scene, and by
his tacit endorsement of Magwitch's instant
transcendence of his own character. displays an
emotional sensitivity out of proportion to the
facts he is presenting to us.
We may recall. and will be dealing with. other
cases of emotional response that seem outside the
range of expected behavior -Pip's earlier aversion
to Magwitch. for instance. And there is no
inidication that Dickens creates these anomalies
436
Lawrence Jay Dessner
within a critical or ironic distancing framework.4
We may shrink from the scene's sentimentality,
but there is nothing in the text to imply that
Dickens does so. Indeed, we may recall a scene,
in the second chapter of Hard Timnes, in which
Sissy Jupe is similarly spotlighted by a ray of
sunshine through windows, and suspect that Pip,
here particularly, is speaking with Dickens' voice.
If the meaning of Great Expectations is moral. or
social, or political, if Pip's saga is, in these ways,
Everyman's saga, is it not crucial that his personality
be within those parameters that strike us,
without hesitation, as "normal," that Pip be one
whose private life does not unduly distort his
vision of general moral and social experience? Is
it not crucial that Dickens, our guide to the generalized
meanings of Pip's life. appear himself
free of personal and private interest in the specifics
of the particular, illustrative case'? Historical,
biographical, economic, cultural, even political
explanations of this problem are available,
but to rely on any of them is to reduce one's
claims for the masterwork or to disregard our
theories of literary value. And even then, are we
convinced that any public, general idea can be
the prime cause of such emotional intensities'?
There are other critical and pedagogical difficulties
with the novel and its critical heritage. It
seems a realistic work, but its plot depends on
contrivance and coincidence. Its moral and
political basis, to the extent that its intent is seen
as moral or political, will not enforce consensus
or always stand scrutiny.5 Problems of this sort
have long since suggested psychological criticism,
investigations of Pip's motivation. It has been
said that Pip indulges in feelings of guilt out of
proportion 'to their proximate cause and that
Dickens uncritically, it seems unwittingly, endorses
this anomaly.6 When young Pip steals for
Magwitch. for instance. the bov acts under the
threat of death and is therefore innocent. The
theft should not initiate years of guilt and the
abiding fear of criminal taint. The incident, however.
is more complex in its embodiment:
"You young dog," said the man, licking his lips,
"what fat cheeks you ha' got."
I believe they were fat, though I was at that time
undersizedf, or my years,a nd not strong.
"Darn Me if I couldn't eat 'em," said the man,
with a threatening shake of his head, "and if I han't
half a mind to't!" (p. 2; Ch. i)
Pip's presentation of the scene. years after the
event, gives us a gruff but playful and teasing
Magwitch. winking at Pip, inviting him and us to
see how comically he is overdoing his threat.7 If
Pip, at that time. saw the "threat" the way he
presents it in his narrative, the boy's thefts from
the Gargery kitchen and forge were iiot committed
under duress. and he then is guilty. a party to a
conspiracy. Surely this reading, is not the one
enforced by the text. Magwitch is in no position
to indulge his sense of humor. Nor does Pip
exhibit anything but fear. On the other hand. as
Pip grows into adulthood, as he re-creates the
scene for us, he should recall and correct his first
impressions of Magwitch and that early sense of
guilt. Yet this is not an adequate summation of
the ways the boy and the plot develop. Pip's sense
of his own guilt does not leave him as he learns
that he is not legally or morally guilty. His guilt
feelings survive their cause, a logical absurdity
that suggests that the cause of Pip's sense of guilt
has been wrongly identified. On the assumption
that Magwitch's threat is what psychoanalysts
would call a "screen memory," a false lead, I will
examine the question of Pip's guilt, with what
help depth psychology can provide, in the hope of
discovering the core of the novel's appeal. what
sort of novel it is, what it is "about."
Complexities lurk in this endeavor. Whose
"screen memory" is misleading the reader as to
the cause of Pip's feelings of guilt'? Pip surely is
responsible, but does Dickens provide us with
materials in the text with which we can fairly be
expected to see through the screen? Or does he
conspire with Pip to disguise something'? And
why is the disguise a relatively poor one? It
prompts, rather than precludes, a closer look.
In the path of the psychoanalytically oriented
study of Great E.pectations is Edmund Wilson's
pioneering psychological essay, "Dickens: The
Two Scrooges."' Wilson is very much an amateur
psychoanalyst. He muddles medical terminology,
speaking here of "trauma," of "obviously neurotic
symptoms" (p. 7). there of "the burningout
of his [Dickens'] nerves" (p. 60). He insists
on biography: "It is necessary to see him as a man
in order to appreciate him as an artist" (p. 9),
and indulges in unscientific. even irresponsible,
psychobiographical speculations. While Freud
pointed investigators of behavior to its preconscious
roots in the first few years of life. Wilson
437
Great Expectations: "the ghost of a man's own father"
points to the twelve-year-old Dickens' relegation
to the blacking warehouse, calls it "trauma"
(p. 7), and asks us to see "the work of Dickens's
whole career" as "an attempt to digest these early
shocks" (p. 8). It is bad psychoanalysis and not
so much bad literary criticism as not literary
criticism at all. It silently defies Freudian ideas of
the formation of personality in infancy, and it
loses the novels in its search for their author.
Orthodox Freudians would say that whatever
traumatic events shaped Dickens' feelings had
occurred long before the shocks of the blacking
warehouse. Few Freudians would say that personality
is fixed forever in infancy. that significant
change and growth do not occur in later life. Most
would agree that the unconscious is exactly that,
un-conscious. It exists, most malleably, before
consciousness. Before Dickens was aware.
through his command of language, of his own
existence, the shape and tendencies of his personality
had largely been developed.
Psychoanalysis is, of course, not possible without
the living patient who bears the tale of his
preconscious emotional life embedded in his
psyche. But psychoanalytic concepts are of use to
literary criticism with the aid of the bridge provided
by Freud and ably treated at length by
Taylor Stoehr and Norman N. Holland: "invented
dreams can be interpreted in the same way
as real ones."9 We may treat Great Expectations
as if it were a dream and expect it to be, like
dreams, coherent in terms of the special logic of
the unconscious. Such an analysis, guided by the
formulations and case histories of psychoanalytic
practice," generates the following thesis: Great
Expectations is about a child's feelings of deprivation
and about his attempts to live at peace with
his special emotional history. We are here assuming
that Pip, a character, not a person, is
nevertheless created so that Freudian principles
apply to his motivation. But Pip is not an autonomous
being; his relationship to Dickens is
close and complex, and, where narrative distance
is indeterminate, ambiguous. The shifting and
complex relationship between author and character,
dreamer and dream, a commonplace of psychoanalytic
practice, has also been described, in
literary terms, in J. Hillis Miller's discussion of
the "intersubjectivity" of Victorian fiction: "A
novel is a temporal rhythm made up of the movement
of the minds of the narrator and his characters
in their dance of approach and withdrawal,
love and hate, convergence and divergence, merger
and division."''
The novel is Dickens' dream; its revelations of
feeling spring from him. Indeed, our analysis of
Pip parallels a psychoanalyst's interpretation of
a real dream Dickens had and described to
John Forster. Dr. Klingerman's summation of his
analysis stresses this basic motif: "The loss of
siblings in early childhood frequently exerts a
profound impact in terms of unresolved guilt and
mourning and the development of restitutive
tendencies."'2 But the narrative, the dream, may
also be seen as Pip's. We are asked to see him as
shaper and teller of his own storv. His dream is
contained within that of Dickens'. It is a (Iream
within a dream, although the abstract statement
of the structure may not suggest that blending and
metamorphosis of scenes and persons, of dream
and dreamer, that common memories of real
dreams remind us of. Perhaps the youth's lines
in Arnold's "The Strayed Reveller" may help
clarify an aspect of this complex relationship between
dreamer and dream, artist and his creation:
"... -such a price / The Gods exact for song: /
To become what we sing." 3
The instance before us. to return to our thesis
that Great Expectations is about feelings of deprivation,
is that of a child who, prior to reaching
the stage of verbalized self-consciousness, lost
parents and siblings. It is as common a pattern as
any in clinical practice. The infant, like Auden's
adult with a "normal heart," "Craves what it
cannot have,/ Not universal love/ But to be
loved alone." He competes for love with uncanny
determination, for he believes that his very existence
depends upon it. Competitors for love he
wishes out of the way, his equivalent for death.
The death or disappearance of parent or sibling in
early childhood fills the infant with fear and guilt.
He believes that his wishes are magical, that they
caused death, and that others know this. The remaining
family members will not love him, a
murderer, so he seeks absolution. He wants punishment
now as much as he wants love.
The loss of both parents and all male siblings,
Pip's case, intensifies the deprivation: there is no
source of love, no agent from whom to receive
punishment. An objection might be raised at
this point: Pip's parents and brothers were dead
before Pip's own birth or, at least, before his
438
Lawrence Jay Dessner
earliest feelings and fantasies. This logical difficulty
would not faze a psychoanalyst. He sees a
pattern of emotional behavior focused. as we shall
see. on the motif of unresolved guilt. and a history.
provided by his patient, that identifies a
traumatic genesis which is denied by the facts.
The pattern of behavior is still there. Its genesis is.
as yet. unknown, but the search for it will be
facilitated by identification of the pattern and by
the useful fact that the history the patient has
offered is a rather subtle piece of subterfuge. The
analyst knows he is on the right track. He knows
how common it is for people, whose parents are
living, to imagine themselves, in their dreams and
daydreams, to be or to have been. young orphans.
The ubiquity of such fantasies is suggested by
many games children play. by thematic analyses
of myths and folklore, and by the number of
novels and romances that incorporate the motif.
A recent student of Charlotte Bronte's novels, all
four of which have an orphan as protagonist,
was moved to make the pattern universal:
"Every reader is an orphan whose family is not
truly his family and who wishes to punish it.
along with other authority figures, for saying no
to him and curbing his desires.""4
Of course. the psychoanalyst. when he learns
that his "patient" is a character in a work of fiction,
would simply assume that the story is a
vehicle for expression of feelings of its creator,
that Pip's history is an emotional correlative of
the unknown psychic history of his creator. This
assumption, questionable or distasteful as it may
strike some. is often made by literary critics and
may be defended or explained by such precepts
as these put forth by J. Hillis Miller: "The writing
of a novel is also a gesture, and this is its primary
reality. It brings into visibility what its author is.
A man is what he does, and this is as true for the
writing of a novel as for any other action" (The
PFor'n7 of' Victorian F'iction, p. 1). What is crucial
for literary criticism is what the author does, his
work's pattern of feeling: diagnosis of its genesis,
why he does it, unless the work encourages our
search for it, is not our goal.
The possible ramifications of feelings of guilt
and deprivation are wondrously complex, but
among the more common reactions is that pattern
in which deprivation comes to be felt as justified:
the loss of love is accepted as a balance to the
guilt, as deserved, even desired, punishment. Related
to this syndrome is behavior that is overtly a
reaching toward love, covertly a mode of selfpreserving
self-abasement. A good deal of Pip's
behavior, particularly with Estella. exhibits this
pattern rather obviously. A child with Pip's psychological
history. and with. perhaps. a theoretical
predisposition to neurosis, will tend to carry
his unfulfilled emotional needs into his adult life.
The intensity with which he pursues psychic
gratifications is tempered only by the necessity to
observe the conventions of adult society. To the
degree that Pip's love of Estella. and the feelings
and behavior it produces. conform to social conventions.
the psychic transaction that it incorporates
is successfully masked or assimilated. To
the degree that Dickens' novel conforms to conventions
of characterization in fiction. he is successful.
To the degree that Pip and Dickens "fail,"
fail to achieve convincing congruity between private
and public acts, this essay is necessary.
Our analysis of Gcreat E.xpectations will show
that Pip's search for love and punishment is
directed primarily toward a father figure who will
love him with constancy and intensity, but who
also will redeem the boy's burden of guilt by
punishing him. Yet the father is the prime competitor
for the love of the life-sustaining mother
and is. therefore, wished out of the way. When he
disappears. the child strives to find him. If he can
be found. the murder is repealed, or did not even
happen. Pip's mother is gone too. Who wished
her away'? The father. The child hates him, strives
to punish him. These motives are obviously,
even in this simplified sketch, self-contradictory.
But. as Leonard F. Manheim formulates the
Freudian dogma, "there is no such thing as logical
incompatibility in the Unconscious."'5 The end
of Pip's search will be the discovery of a father
who will love and punish him, and whom the boy
can love and punish. The intensity of these
strivings pushes them to their logical, if grotesquely
amoral and seemingly self-defeating
limits: the logical extension, the ideal case. of love
is self-sacrifice. suicide: the logical extension of
punishment is murder. Through metaphor and by
analogy, Pip achieves both.
We are rather obviously directed toward this
psychic portrait by the novel's first few pages. It is
as if Dickens were the busy psychoanalyst's ideal
patient. He lays out, in the first session, a barely
disguised self-diagnosis.'" The novel begins, not
439
Great Expectations: "the ghost of a man's own father"
with Pip's birth or with his genealogy, but with
his birth into consciousness and literacy. Its first
episode is the earliest available to the narrator's
memory. Its first words are a reference to "my
father." Its first complex of feelings include the
pathos of the orphan who "never saw my father
or mother." and that pathos is complemented by
the setting among tombstones "on a memorable
raw afternoon towards evening." It is accentuated
by the five "lozenges" which mark Pip's five
dead brothers. and by the archness of tone. bordering
on self-pity, the mock innocence of the
narrator's language, itself mocked by ironic wit:
To five little stone lozenges, each about a foot and a half
long, which were arranged in a neat row beside their
grave, and were sacred to the memory of five little
brothers of mine who gave up trying to get a living
exceedingly early in that universal struggle-I am
indebtedf or a belief I religiouslye ntertainedt hat they
had all been born on their back with their hands in their
trousers-pocketsa,n d had nevert akent hem out in this
state of existence. (p. 1; Ch. i)
The wit mitigates the paragraph's sentimentality
and saves Pip from the full measure of pain his
memories prompt. (It also introduces a dominant
metaphor of the novel's public, political, level of
meaning: survival of personality is figured as
economic survival.) But Pip's world is harsh and
torbidding, and the child, as he sees the earliest
landscape he can remember. as he re-creates his
earliest intimations of his own distinct identity,
discovers himself to be "beginning to cry" (p. 1;
Ch. i).
The mode of presentation of Pip's story changes
here on the verge of his tears. The child, alone
with his private thoughts, in a realistically rendered
world, is immediately enmeshed in a society
of other people. including mythic or fairytale
people, and a world worked by the conventions
of melodrama and romance. The deprivations
of the orphan and sole surviving son to
which the first page points and which is. in this
reading. the core of the novel, propel no further
confessional self-diagnosis. What follows is a
drastically edited confession. almost a translation
into modes of discourse which disguise and yet
hint at the novel's private impetus.
From this point on. our procedure is simply to
test our psychological reading of the private
impetus of Great E.xpecitattions against the evidence
which is, theoretically, the entire text. Such
testing would require an impossibly long article.
The alternative is to take samplings which could
have been taken at random with a theoretically
perfect case--and a perfect analyst. One may
begin with Pip and his toying with a central question
of child-rearing. He loves the joke about
being brought up "by hand." It ironically implies
that especially loving care had been expended on
his behalf; it implies, without irony. that a good
deal of physical punishment went with it. But
beneath the joke-are all Pip's jokes defensive
masks'?--is the pain of infantile deprivation. To
bring up "by hand" also means: "to feed by
bottle or spoon rather than at the breast.""7 Oh
that "square impregnable bib in front, . . . stuck
full of pins and needles" which covers the only
maternal breasts Pip has known. And then how
sadly touching is the mock innocence, the comic
and pathetic archness of Pip's bewildered complaint
on his sister's bib: "Though I really see no
reason why she should have worn it at all; or
why. if she did wear it at all, she should not have
taken it off every day of her life" (p. 6; Ch. ii).
Or one can go to the peripheral domestic
comedy of the Pocket family. The rearing of the
seven (p. 176; Ch. xxii) little Pockets, an echo of
the seven little Pirrips, is chaotic enough to
prompt their father's outcry: "Are infants to be
nutcrackered into their tombs. and is nobody to
save them ?" (p. 183; Ch. xxiii). The youngest child
is heard "wailing dolefully" and then "by degrees
... was hushed and stopped, as if it were a
young ventriloquist with something in its mouth"
(p. 176; Ch. xxii). Does not this comic description
elucidate Pip's fear of his own extinction'?
Like the youngest surviving Pirrip. baby Pocket
gets not milk from his mother but needles. a
needle-case being supplied as a pacifier: "And
more needles were missing than it could be regarded
as quite wholesome for a patient of such
tender years either to apply externally or to take
as a tonic" (p. 257; Ch. xxxiii).
This branch of the Pocket family is but one of
the novel's subsidiary families through whom
Pip's psychic history is recalled and obliquely expressed.
The pattern of childhood deprivation
and familial conflict is widely apparent although
sometimes indirectly presented. Joe Gargery's
father "went off in a purple leptic fit." but not before
terrorizing his wife and child so thoroughly
440
Lawrence Jay Dessner
that they, "several times," ran away from him
(p. 42; Ch. vii). Miss Havisham "was a spoilt
child. Her mother died when she was a baby"
(p. 169; Ch. xxii). Her own half-brother plotted
against her, and was crazed with remorse for it as
he died (p. 331; Ch. xlii). Biddy "was an orphan
like myself; like me, too, had been brought up by
hand" (p. 40; Ch. vii). Magwitch: "I've no more
notion where I was born. than you have-if so
much" (p. 328; Ch. xlii). Estella, of course, was
abandoned by her parents, but her laughter at the
machinations of the grasping Pocket relations
strikes Pip as being "too much for the occasion."
Yes, she explains, her bitterness masks remembered
pain: "For you were not brought up in that
strange house from a mere baby.-I was. You
had not your little wits sharpened by the intriguing
against you, suppressed and defenceless, under
the mask of sympathy and pity and what not,
that is soft and soothing" (p. 253; Ch. xxxiii). (It
is ironic that she is so sure Pip's childhood was
different from her own, for as she describes her
childhood it reminds us of Pip's.) Clara Barley's
surviving parent, her father, is a ferocious and
utterly self-centered bully and drunkard. She
tends him with resignation and love. It is understood
that her marriage cannot take place as long
as her father lives: her engagement cannot even
be mentioned to him (p. 355; Ch. xlvi). She submits
without any trace of antagonism. Herbert
Pocket is pleased "to love a girl who has no relations"
(p. 355; Ch. xlvi), his own being a burden
to him, and he wonders whether "the children of
not exactly suitable marriages [like himself and
his "poor sister Charlotte who was next me and
died before she was fourteen"] are always most
particularly anxious to be married" (p. 237; Ch.
xxx).
Like the dome of many-colored glass, Pip's
emotional plight colors all within his range. As in
any work of art, or any dream, the theme is pervasive,
reduplicated in many contexts, unifying.
That the Oedipal motifs in Great ELpectations.
had a deeply personal resonance t'or himself
Dickens would have denied. He said, although
with a suggestive ambiguity. that he could never
dream of his characters since "it would be like a
man dreaming of himself, which is clearly an impossibility.
Things exterior to one's self must always
be the basis of dreams." Manheim. after
quoting Dickens here. counters with a restatement
of a broadly accepted Freudian principle: "It is
impossible for one to dream of anything hitt one's
self."18 Perhaps Hopkins' line, and the poem from
which it comes. has a useful pertinence here:
. . . What I do is me. . . 11 9
We know little of Wopsle's past. but he does
say grace in a style "something like a religious
cross of the Ghost in Hamlet with Richard the
Third" (p. 22; Ch. iv). His interest in these violent
tragedies of family life is presented as grandly
comic, but his performance as Hamlet depresses
Pip, who thereupon "dreamed that my expectations
were all cancelled, and that I had to give my
hand in marriage to Herbert's Clara, or play Hamlet
to Miss Havisham's Ghost, before twenty
thousand people, without knowing twenty words
of it," a nightmare of terror and panic as Pip identifies
himself with Shakespeare's troubled Prince
(p. 244; Ch. xxxi). Wemmick's idyllic relationship
with his "Aged Parent" is the other side ot the
coin, a father-son relationship from which all
traces of competitiveness have been repressed.20
Dolge Orlick, Pip's nemesis and alter ego.21
"slouches" in and out of the forge "like Cain" the
fratricide (p. 105; Ch. xv). Trabb's boy. despite
his antic satire of Pip's pretensions, is an epitome
of the disenfranchised child. He lacks a logical
target for his revenge; he lacks even the dignity of
a name.
No doubt these and most other soundings of
the text can be assimilated to other sorts of interpretation.
but none comprehend nearly so
much of the text, or do so with as much consistency.
Nor do they account for the power of
Great Expectations, the hold the book has had on
its broad readership. That derives from the personal
obsession at its center. And this obsession,
disguised by public themes and by the excitements
of the suspense plot. is remarkably obvious and
pervasive. It is a question not of depth analysis
but of a particular sort of alertness to the surface
of the text. Pip, who gives no more than a sketch
of his early childhood, assumes, from time to
time, that we know much more about it than we
do. How often and how frankly does he allude to a
feeling of "dread ... the revival for a few minutes
of the terror of childhood" (p. 217; Ch. xxviii).
It is hardly daring to suggest that the genesis ot
art is personal and private, emotional rather than
rational. In fact, all writing is, in some sense,
automatic writing. My pen moves only in the
441
Great Expectations: "the ghost of a man's own father"
interstices between periods of thought. I think,
ergo I am-but in that instant the pen stops. I
write-and where is that self-conscious "I" of
which I am so fond'? Some works of art baffle attempts
to locate their personal impetus; the dream
carries the emotive charge while obscuring its
private basis. Many other works, some call them
"confessional," seem to deal exclusively and
courageously with their personal impetus, although
one may. remembering the saw that no
one can psychoanalyze himself, doubt their sincerity
or their claim to sophistication. What is remarkable
is the way Dickens covers his private
traces while letting many of the cats out of the
bag. It is as if the critical problems with the novel,
its failures as it were, were deliberate, the infant's
cry piercing the artist's manly reserve. It is as if
Dickens wants us to see through the disguise, as if
he wants, himself, to deal directly with private
and taboo subjects but will not quite acknowledge
this desire. He winks at us: "Yes, yes, Pip is Me"-
but only winks. If we wink back, as if to join the
conspiracy, he looks away. He wants to get caught
but he lacks that extra measure of courage that
would enable him to turn himself in. Jay Leyda,
writing of Melville's stories, has described a
similar drama: "We are compelled to regard
these stories as an artist's resolution of that constant
contradiction--between the desperate need
to communicate and the fear of revealing too
much."22
Pip not only feels guilty, he tells us that he feels
guilty. Often he tells us that he cannot understand
why his feelings of guilt occur or why they are so
strong. Often he tries to discover why, or announces
that the discovery is either impossible or
inconsequential. It is as if Pip's telling of his story
and Dickens' writing of the novel are acts that incorporate
psychological probing, discovery, and
obfuscation. One thinks of Philip Roth's Portnov's
Complaint and his even more obviously
relevant Ml Lif/ as a Man. Roth's protagonists
recount their histories, the one to his psychoanalyst,
the other to readers of fiction and autobiography,
the recounting being clearly seen by
both author and reader as forms of self-defense,
discovery, and therapy. Roth's distance from his
protagonists and his awareness of their psychological
maneuverings are clear and constant.
Dickens' awareness is ambiguous and wavering.
Pip himself is fascinated by the recurring "inexplicable
feeling" associated with the "poor
labyrinth" of his secret life (pp. 259, 219; Chs.
xxxiii, xxix). "What I wanted, who can say'? How
can I say, when I never knew'?" (p. 101; Ch. xiv).
"I consumed the whole time in thinking how
strange it was that I should be encompassed by all
this taint of prison and crime" (p. 249; Ch. xxxii).
"I thought how miserable I was, but hardly knew
why, or how long I had been so, or on what day of
the week I made the reflection, or even who I was
that made it" (p. 311; Ch. xl). "Yet Estella was so
inseparable from all my restlessness and disquiet
of mind, that I really fell into confusion as to the
limits of my own part in its production" (p. 258;
Ch. xxxiv). From time to time this sort of probing
into the forbidden center of Pip's psyche is expressed
by a pun: "I may here remark that I suppose
myself to be better acquainted than any living
authority, with the ridgy effect of a weddingring,
passing unsympathetically over the human
countenance" (p. 48; Ch. vii). Or even by a sexual
double entendre: "Conscience is a dreadful thing
when it accuses man or boy; but when, in the case
of a boy, that secret burden co-operates with another
secret burden down the leg of his trousers,
it is (as I can testify) a great punishment" (p. 10;
Ch. ii). Sometimes a character other than Pip has
the innocent-sounding but reverberating line. As
does Camilla Pocket: "I am determined not to
make a display of my feelings, but it's very hard to
be told one wants to feast on one's relations" (p.
82; Ch. xi). Or as does Joe Gargery: "Which I
meantersay, if the ghost of a man's own father
cannot be allowed to claim his attention, what
can, Sir'?" (pp. 208-09; Ch. xxvii). I do not believe
such quotations can justly be said to be out
of context. The entire novel, all its characters and
incidents, springs from one center; each part is an
appropriate context for any other part.23
It is in the plot, however, that the Oedipal
drama, so often alluded to by various characters,
may be glimpsed. Pip needs to find a parent figure
whom he can love, and fear, and kill, and who will
in turn terrorize, and succumb to, and lovingly
pardon him. Magwitch is the perfection of that
figure. The plot traces Pip's experience of discovering
this. But the psyche takes what nourishment
it can, makes do, along the way. It does not
put off immediate though partial satisfactions in
anticipation of larger rewards. Psychic transactions
are entered into with all comers. Mrs. Joe,
442
Lawrence Jay Dessner
to be sure, has much the test of the bargain with
Pip. She claims and disclaims, at her own pleasure,
the rewards due Pip's parents: "If it warn't
for me you'd have been to the churchyard long
ago, and stayed there..... It's bad enough to be a
blacksmith's wife (and him a Gargery) without
being your mother" (p. 7; Ch. ii). Sibling and
maternal antagonisms merge in the threat of
murder/abandonment. Dickens steps in to redress
the balance by having Orlick mortally attack
her. And the forgiveness she both gives and
asks at her death is ambiguous enough to include
Pip: "And so she presently said 'Joe' again, and
once 'Pardon,' and once 'Pip'
"
(p. 269; Ch.
xxxv).
Miss Hlavisham permits herself, while assuming
the role of Pip's benefactor, to torment him.
Because of her wealth, her age, and her pitiful
condition, and because of her approximation to a
parental figure, Pip's aggressiveness toward her
can only be admitted through his hallucinated
visions of her death by hanging (pp. 58-59, 380;
Chs. viii, xlix). The intensity of his emotional reaction
to her can also be seen in his ludicrous narration
to his family circle of his first encounter
with her: "She was sitting ... in a black velvet
coach.... And Miss Estella... handed her in
cake and wine at the coach-window, on a gold
plate.... Four dogs... fought for veal-cutlets
out of a silver basket" (pp. 62-63; Ch. ix). Pip
tries, without success, to explain why he so grotesquely
and seemingly gratuitously embellished
his tale: "'f a dread of not being understood be
hidden in the breasts of other young people to
anything like the extent to which it used to be
hidden in mine--which I consider probable, as I
have no particular reason to suspect myself of
having been a monstrosity-it is the key to many
reservations" (p. 61; Ch. ix). And after Miss
Havisham is known not to be Pip's patron-parent,
Pip saves her from death by fire, saves her, but in
this language: "We were on the ground struggling
like desperate enemies, and . . . the closer I
covered her. the more wildly she shrieked and
tried to free herself" (p. 380; Ch. xlxi). The violence
and sexual ambiguity of this strikes Pip, as
well as us, as excessive and he tries to discover its
genesis. He refers it to unconscious, irrational,
and, to his relief, inaccessible motives: "That this
occurred I knew through the result, but not
through anything I felt, or thought, or knew I did.
I knew nothing until I knew that we were on the
floor.... Assistance was sent for, and I heid her
until it came, as if I unreasonably fancied (I think
I did) that if I let her go, the fire would break out
again and consume her" (pp. 380-81; Ch. xlix).
Pumblechook is a parody of the surrogate
father, linked, by the motif of handshaking, with
Magwitch. His various claims to be Pip's benefactor
and his actual negligence of the boy come
to us, through Pip's reportage, as farce, their pain
distanced into triumphant comedy, and this despite,
rather than because of, Pumblechook's long
and close relationship with him. He is "Joe's
uncle, but Mrs. Joe appropriated him" (p. 21;
Ch. iv). He is by this metaphor, and metaphor is
as good as fact for the psyche, a blood relative.
His cruelty is not forgotten. Orlick, an agent of
Pip's repressed aggression, punishes and humiliates
him: "They took his till, and they took his
cash-box, and they drinked his wine, and they
partook of his wittles, and they slapped his face,
and they pulled his nose, and they tied him up to
his bedpust, and they giv' him a dozen, and they
stuffed his mouth full of flowering annuals" (p.
442; Ch. lvii). That is Joe's narrative. Its cadence
has the pulse of ritual utterance, an exultant folk
exorcism.
Jaggers is an interesting variation on the
theme. He has personal force and authority and
the identification with the law that Manheim has
written about as symbolic of Oedipal relationships.
24 He is, in legal fact, a surrogate for both
Magwitch and Miss Havisham and the immediate
provider of the mysterious largesse. But he is
unwilling to engage in any psychological transactions
with Pip. His interest is professional.
without affect. He washes his hands of personal
involvement. And since he will not play the games
most people play, Pip's relationship with him is a
dead end. He will neither love Pip nor hate him
(either one would do), and so Pip is rarely engaged
by him more intimately than as an object of
curiosity. At an early interview with Jaggers, Pip
"felt at a disadvantage, which reminded me of
that old time when I had been put upon a tombstone"
(p. 272; Ch. xxxvi). Pip is probing, trying
to assimilate Jaggers into his psychic life. He is
made "intensely melancholy" by the encounter,
he says, but Jaggers' potential to provoke feelings
of guilt is insubstantial, and Pip steps aside and
transfers him to Herbert Pocket. Pip sees Herbert,
443
Great Expectations: "the ghost of a man's own father"
as he sees everyone, as a version of his own emotional
position, and he derives some slight gratification
when Herbert "thought he must have
committed a felony and forgotten the details of it,
he felt so dejected and guilty" (p. 278; Ch. xxxvi).
Pip's search for the special kind of father figure
his psyche requires extends into many other
nooks and crannies of the novel, but the most
decisive encounters are those with Joe Gargery
and with Magwitch. Gargery. as the husband of
Pip's acting imother, is the most obvious Iather
figure, and he is in some respects what Pip craves.
Submissiveness, humility, loving-kindness, Joe is
their perfection. "I always treated him as a larger
species of child" (p. 7; Ch. ii), says Pip. He is the
least threatening, least competitive, most selfsacrificing
of men: and despite the brawn of his
blacksmith's arm, the least masculine.25 There is
not the least hint, until the novel's close, of his
having a sexual nature. He is more like Pip's child
than Pip's father, a reversal of roles similar to that
of Wemmick and Aged Parent, a not uncommon
motif in Dickens.26 But Pip needs more than this.
He needs a father whom he can hurt and who will
hurt him, before whom he can feel guilt and suffer
punishment. Joe Gargery is incapable of anger,
but Pip can only learn this by attempting to provoke
his anger. Failing that, he punishes him for
his "refusal" to play the stern father part to Pip's
satisfaction. Both stances taken toward Gargery
can exist at the same time, in the same act, without
respect to the logic of cause and effect that reason
requires. "Past, present and future are threaded,"
says Freud, "on the string of the wish that runs
through them all."27 The psyche never gives up,
never admits that any defeat is final, never is disloyal,
as it were, to the demands that propel it.
The text shows us Pip probing Joe's character,
seeking not knowledge but reaction, reaction
specifically in the form of retributive anger, the
exhibition of pain and vindictive, guilt-provoking,
guilt-satisfying, response. Joe's pardon is not
enough, for Joe will not be hurt; his love for Pip
is not offered in spite of the pain Pip causes him,
nor even with awareness of any cruelty on Pip's
part. His acceptance does not have the force of
forgiveness. Pip's assault on Joe takes the forms
of condescension and direct attack, both masked
by a sentimentalized affection. As Pip paints him,
Joe's stupidity is only matched by his grotesque
appearance and his unexampled lack of social
confidence: "I never knew Joe to remember anything
from one Sunday to another, or to acquire,
under my tuition, any piece of information whatever.
Yet he would smoke his pipe at the Battery
with a far more sagacious air than anywhere else
-even with a learned air-as if he considered
himself to be advancing immensely" (p. 102; Ch.
xv). "He pulled up his shirt-collar so very high behind,
that it made the hair on the crown of his
head stand up like a tuft of feathers. ... Joe took
his hat off and stood weighing it by the brim in
both his hands: as if he had some urgent reason in
his mind for being particular to half a quarter of
an ounce" (p. 93; Ch. xiii). Joe does not take
offense at such ridicule. No provocation or punishment
hurts him. Pip's only recourse, the only
use he can make of the man who will not blame
him, is to blame himself, on Joe's behalf, for
imagined treachery and disloyalty to Joe. This
permits Pip to castigate himself and to profit by
encounters with the oblivious Joe.
The sentimentality of the procedure's enactment
signals Pip's strained frustration: "Heaven
knows we need never be ashamed of our tears, for
they are rain upon the blinding dust of earth,
overlying our hard hearts. I was better after I had
cried, than before-more sorry, more aware of
my own ingratitude, more gentle. If I had cried
before, I should have had Joe with me then" (p.
151; Ch. xix). The charge Pip brings against himself
here we all know to be patent nonsense, although
Dickens does not let Pip, or himself, see
clearly through the tears. "But, sharpest and
deepest pain of all-it was for the convict, guilty
of I knew not what crimes, and liable to be taken
out of those rooms where I sat thinking, and
hanged at the Old Bailey door, that I had deserted
Joe.... In every rage of wind and rush of rain, I
heard pursuers" (pp. 307-08; Ch. xxxix). Do we
not hear a note, in this, of what a recent survey of
Psychoanalytic Theory and Therapy of Masochism
calls The Joy of Su/ffring?28 It serves, as does
Pip's hopeless pursuit of Estella, to lacerate a
psyche which in its "innermost life of my life"
(p. 223; Ch. xxix) desires to be scourged. Pip's
"condition of unreason" (p. 245; Ch. xxxii), to
use another of his descriptions of his emotional
plight, has demanded it. He makes what capital
he can of Joe, but Joe is found wanting and Pip
takes it out on him. His intended proposal to
Biddy is his revenge on Joe for being Joe. Only
444
La'wreniCe Ja i' Dessner
after Magwitch's death are Joe and Biddy allowed
their fair measure of respect. Only after
Pip's devils have been assuaged by, most importantly,
the catastrophe of the Magwitch relationship
can Biddy and Joe be given, be seen as having,
adult sexuality.
The assertion that Pip harbors patricidal tendencies.
that in some ways he accomplishes acts
of patricide on Mrs. Joe, Miss Havisham, and
Magwitch, may still seem a shockingly askew
judgment. Pip is gentle, sober, nonviolent, not
that sort of fellow at all. The theory that Oedipal
aggressions color all personalities may evaporate
before the novel's display of Pip's growing into
various forms of loving-kindness toward those
whose lives cross his. On the other hand, the text
presents a number of untimely and violent deaths.
and is not the amalgam of Pip and Dickens, who
makes it all up, responsible for all of it? Freud
said the patient is responsible for his own dreams
-surely the analyst isn't! In the world of fiction
the narrator-author is the first cause of all events.
Pip often suspects himself of being a murderer, or
meditates, in various degrees of seriousness, on
the possibility. Mr. Wopsle involves Pip in a
reading, in Pumblechook's parlor, of "the affecting
tragedy of George Barnwell." The hero of
Lillo's very popular play, parodied by Thackeray
in Punch in 1847, robs his master and murders his
uncle. Pip plays the murderer: "At once ferocious
and maudlin, I was made to murder my uncle
with no extenuating circumstances whatever" (p.
110). Pumblechook glares at him "saying 'Take
warning, boy, take warning!' as if it were a wellknown
fact that I contemplated murdering a near
relation, provided I could only induce one to have
the weakness to become my benefactor" (p. 110;
Ch. xv). How recklessly does Pip express the inexpressible,
a murderer tempting fate, inviting
capture, by returning to the scene of his crime. It
is, in this case, not the first such return. Earlier,
when Pumblechook, expecting brandy, choked
on the tar-water, young Pip was terrified: "I
didn't know how I had done it, but I had no doubt
I had murdered him somehow" (p. 25; Ch. iv).
The Barnwell play is followed directly by news
of the assault on Mrs. Joe. Pip takes it this way:
"With my head full of George Barnwell, I was at
first disposed to believe that I must have had some
hand in the attack upon my sister, or at all events
that as her near relation, popularly known to be
under obligations to her, I was a more legitimate
object of suspicion than any one else" (p. 113;
Ch. xvi). Pip immediately reconsiders, taking a
"view of the case, which was more reasonable."
But years later, hearing footsteps on his stairsthey
are Magwitch's-Pip reverts to the earlier,
unreasonable idea: "What nervous folly made me
start, and awfully connect it with the footsteps of
my dead sister, matters not" (p. 299; Ch. xxxix).
"Matters not"! Of course it matters, and Pip
senses that it does. What he implies by the phrase
is something like this: "Reader, you and I both
know a good deal more than we admit about
these psychological strategies of mine. They are,
in fact, so obvious and so distasteful, and I can do
nothing about them. I'm sorry to have been tactless
again and to have made explicit reterence to
them. Please excuse me and forget it ever happened."
Pip's nonchalance here is itself strategic,
defensive. Herbert warns Pip that Magwitch
might turn himself in to the police if he feels Pip
has forsaken him. Pip has not thought of abandoning
Magwitch at all, but Herbert's speculation
opens the old wound: "1 was so struck by the
horror of this idea, which had weighed upon me
from the first, and the working out of which
would make me regard myself, in some sort, as his
murderer, that I could not rest in my chair, but
began pacing to and fro" (p. 325; Ch. xli).
Pip's relationship to Magwitch is the fulcrum
of the novel's movement. It begins with Magwitch's
comic ferocity: "Keep still, you little
devil, or I'll cut your throat!" (p. 2: Ch. i). Pip
misreads his man's immediate motive, but responds
with sensitivity to him: "As I saw him go,
picking his way among the nettles, and among the
brambles that bound the green mounds [The intensity
with which this is felt forces the prose into
verse], he looked in my young eyes as if he were
eluding the hands of the dead people, stretching
up cautiously out of their graves. to get a twist
upon his ankle and pull him in" (p. 4; Ch. i). The
living man, through imagery, is linked with the
dead Pirrips. Pip keeps from Joe any knowledge
of his pilfering for Magwitch. His reasons for doing
so are obviously strained: "I mistrusted that
if I did, he would think me worse than I was" (p.
37; Ch. vi). Pip knows this rationale is falsely
based, he calls it "morbid." But the convict is recaptured
and the subject drops. Pip transfers his
suffering over "the smart without a name" (p. 57;
445
Great Expectations: "the ghost of a man's own father"
Ch. viii) to the immediately available person,
Estella. That movement reaches its emotional
climax when she tells Pip of her engagement to
Drummle. Pip's response is to restate his love for
her, and, more oddly, his praise and thanksgiving
for her goodness to him: "In this separation I associate
you only with the good.... Oh, God
bless you, God forgive you!" In an "ecstasy of
unhappiness," Pip abases himself before Estella,
praises her, accepts for himself a lifetime of painfully
unrequited love, and forgives her for it all.
"The rhapsody welled up within me, like blood
from an inward wound, and gushed out" (p. 345;
Ch. xliv). Conventions of Victorian romantic love
serve to disguise the intensity of Pip's reactions
here just as the canons of respectability provide a
"cover" for Pip's morbid fear of criminal taint.
We have already noticed some of Pip's early,
intensely felt reactions to Magwitch. As the hint
is given that the returned convict is, as he soon
says, Pip's "second father," Pip's heart beats
"like a heavy hammer of disordered action." He
"had to struggle for every breath." He "seemed
to be suffocating.... The abhorrence in which I
held the man, the dread I had of him, the repugnance
with which 1 shrank from him, could not
have been exceeded if he had been some terrible
beast.... I recoiled from his touch as if he had
been a snake ... while my blood ran cold within
me" (pp. 303-05; Ch. xxxix). To ascribe such intensity
to Pip's sense of class distinctions is to
take the complaint for the diagnosis.
Pip meditates on his case, and on his symptoms,
admitting his inability to verbalize his feelings, yet
fascinated by them: "Words cannot tell what a
sense I had, at the same time, of the dreadful
mystery that he was to me" (p. 319; Ch. xl). "The
imaginary student pursued by the misshapen
creature he had impiously made, was not more
wretched than J, pursued by the creature who had
made me, and recoiling from him with a stronger
repulsion, the more he admired me and the fonder
he was of me" (p. 320; Ch. xl). How accurate is
this description of the minuet of the heart's affections!
And how courageous not to repress the
hint, in the allusion to Mary Shelley's Frankenstein,
that the monster is a creation of the suffering
psyche, a creation that punishes its creator.
Pip is haunted by the idea of being "in some
sort... [Magwitch's] murderer" (p. 352; Ch.
xli). His dreams are of this, he says. He wakes,
"unrefreshed," and "waking.. never lost that
fear" (p. 326; Ch. xli). In the sense that the narrator
invents the novel, he is the murderer. But he
also invents Compeyson. the actual murderer and
his secret surrogate. This link between Pip and
Compeyson is hidden in the plot's complexities,
and yet, like so many hidden connections in
Great Expectations, it is indirectly revealed.
Wopsle, seeing the two of them in his audience
"had a ridiculous fancy that he must be with you,
Mr. Pip, till I saw that you were quite unconscious
of him, sitting behind you there like a ghost" (p.
364; Ch. xlvii). Wopsle, whose foolishness disguises
his insight here, "had from the first vaguely
associated him with me, and known him as somehow
belonging to me in the old village time" (p.
366; Ch. xlvii). "Somehow" and "vaguely," passwords
of sentimental diffuseness, are as explicit
as Pip is able to be.
By the time Magwitch is mortally injured and
apprehended, Pip's "repugnance to him had all
melted away." He sees him as "only ... a man
who had meant to be my benefactor. and who had
felt affectionately, gratefully, and generously,
towards me with great constancy through a series
of years" (p. a23: Ch. liv). With Magwitch's
death doubly assured, Pip can turn to him with
love and for love. Pip's guilt is not utterly "melted
away," but it is assuaged in part by his earlier refusal
to consider taking possession of the wealth
Magwitch had amassed for him. Jaggers "was
querulous and angry with me for having 'let it slip
through my fingers,'" although he admits the
difficulty of Pip's claim. Pip resolves not to try.
Had he tried earlier, the chances would have been
better. Oddly enough, his case would have been
best made had he been related to Magwitch by a
"recognizable tie"-as an adopted son, for instance,
or even as Estella's husband, and so, sonin-
law (pp. 425--26; Ch. lv). Magwitch, in returning
to England, had, in effect, sacrificed himself
for Pip. Pip sacrifices economic security. Magwitch's
money, honestly earned, should be at least
as acceptable as Miss Havisham's inherited
brewery fortune, but neither Pip nor Dickens is
as interested in the evils of snobbery as the surface
of the novel has prompted some of its critics to be.
By refusing to consider laying hold of Magwitch's
wealth before it is too late, Pip frustrates
his benefactor's love and life work. Since he keeps
this fact from Magwitch, the argument that Pip
446
Lawlrence Jay Dessner
deliberately frustrates his patron is solipsistic,
but that is the way of the ego. Pip's realization
that he is "in debt" with "scarcely any money"
brings on acute anxiety: "Then there came one
night which appeared of great duration, and
which teemed with anxiety and horror; and when
in the morning I tried to sit up in my bed and
think of it, I found I could not do so" (p. 437; Ch.
lvii). Pip recovers from his sudden and severe illness
and goes off, chastened but cheerful, to accept
his punishment: eleven years of exile, celibacy,
and only moderately rewarding toil for
Clarriker and Co.
The exchange of loving sacrifice is unequal; the
bargain, at last, in Pip's favor. He has found his
stern, dread-provoking father, and, with Dickens'
help, engineered a socially acceptable patricide,
his victim's forgiveness, and the opportunity to
say over his deathbed: "It was dreadful to think
that I could not be sorry at heart for his being
badly hurt, since it was unquestionably best that
he should die" (p. 423; Ch. liv). Parallel to this acceptance
of patricide is Herbert's situation. He
cannot marry Clara Barley until her father's
death. Pip felt "that Herbert's way was clearing
fast, and that old Bill Barley had but to stick to
his pepper and rum, and his daughter would soon
be happily provided for" (p. 395; Ch. lii). Old
Barley is, eight pages before Magwitch's death,
fading. "Not to say an unfeeling thing," says
Pip, "he cannot do better than go" (p. 427; Ch.
Iv).
Magwitch dies blessing Pip: "You've never deserted
me, dear boy" (p. 435; Ch. Ivi). This, of
course, ignores Pip's initial repulsion, but it reverberates
with echoes of Pip's supposed desertion
of Joe, with Wemmick's treatment of his
aged parent, with, indeed, a large part of the
novel's content. At Magwitch's end, Pip tells him
that Estella, the daughter he deserted, lives. Magwitch
kisses Pip's hand and dies. Pip prays over
the body in the equivocal words of the Pharisee
(Luke xviii.10-13). The equivocation, about
which critics have argued,29 marks an epoch in
this equivocal relationship.
Magwitch dies, but there is a sequel in which
Pip's muted, residual guilt finds expression. With
Magwitch gone, he turns to Joe Gargery: "Oh
Joe, you break my heart! Look angry at me, Joe.
Strike me, Joe. Tell me of my ingratitude. Don't
be so good to me!" (p. 439; Ch. lvii). The absurdity
of imploring Joe to strike him! As David
Goldknopf says: "If the novel can be said to have
a generic moral it is: the heart has its reasons, and
those reasons will fight reason, experience, and
fact, to man's dying breath" ( The Lilf of the Notel,
p. 5).
The working out of Pip's psychological distress
involves a good deal more than those few episodes
discussed here. The exorcism of his feelings of
guilt requires symbolic, purifying deaths by fire
and by water, and, through Orlick's attempt on
his life, the threat of obliteration in the limekiln.
With the novel's end comes the resolution of Pip's
search for parental surrogates. He receives forgiveness
and utterly superfluous promises never
to blame him again from Joe and Biddy (p. 455;
Ch. lviii), and then, after the passage of years, Pip
is reborn as their child. It is told as a dream, a
hallucination: "I touched [the latch] so softly that
I was not heard, and I looked in unseen. There,
smoking his pipe in the old place by the kitchen
firelight, as hale and as strong as ever. though a
little grey, sat Joe; and there. fenced into the
corner with Joe's leg, and sitting on my own little
stool looking at the fire, was-I again!" (p. 457;
Ch. lix). Pip exists again, as a young boy. with
loving and living parents, without the psychological
complications of his first incarnation. The
two Pips--one could as well refer to them in the
singular--return to the graves of their original
parents and the comic play of the novel's first page
is reprised. Pip finds peace, but scars remain. He
will not marry, he says; the last chapter, either
version, is window dressing. He will be sober and
sad, and loyal, another emasculated Joe. He will
meditate on his life and then explain it to us and
to himself, as well as he can. Grelt Expectations
is that explanation.
The explanation tells us how it has felt, how it
feels "now" to remember it and tell it. It does not,
explicitly, tell us why things happened as they did,
although it often is on the verge of discovering a
more adequate rationale than its surface projects.
The secret of Pip's "innermost life of my life"
(p. 223; Ch. xxix) is embedded in the fiction. After
all the novel's secrets have been solved, as Chesterton
said about Dickens' works in general, wc
have the sense "that even the author was unaware
of what was really going on, and when [the plot's
secrets are unraveled,] we simply do not believe."
It is as if those characters "were keeping some-
447
Great Expectations: "the ghost of a man's own father"
thing back from the author as well as from the
reader."30 Beneath the Oedipal secret that we
have all felt as we have felt the novel's power,
there are other secrets for which language and
comprehension are not yet. At Miss Havisham's
death she begs forgiveness, and then: "She said
innumerable times in a low solemn voice. 'What
have I done!' And then, 'When she first came, I
meant to save her from misery like mine.' And
then, 'Take the pencil and write under my name,
"I forgive her"!' She never changed the order of
these three sentences, but she sometimes left out a
word in one or other of them; never putting in another
word, but always leaving a blank and going
on to the next word" (pp. 381--82; Ch. xlix). Perhaps
some Dickensian will accept the challenge
Pip puts to us here and find the arrangement of
those words that will reveal more about what Pip
calls "the sharpest crying of all" (p. 224; Ch. xxix).
Despite such recalcitrant material, I believe
this psychoanalytic reading provides a unified
explanation of this novel's central meaning and
of the incongruities between the novel and received
critical accounts of it. We might do well to
call Great Expectations a "personal novel" rather
than a realistic one. Pip's excessive guilt and those
excesses and anomalies it generates point to
Dickens' personal feelings incompletely assimilated
into the novel's realistic texture, the child's
heart and the child's special and amoral modes of
logic intruding into the controlled distances of
art. Contrivances of plot, inconsistencies of moral
and political thought, and discrepancies of characterization
are functional when we read the
novel aright.
When the novel's surface makes us uneasy with
its apparent intent, forces us to learn more about
the work than its creator gives evidence of knowing,
we may hesitate to award the praise reserved
for those works of supreme esthetic perfection.
Whatever loss this decision entails, it does bring
forward to our attention a compelling biographical
drama. Grealt E.xpectations makes us spectators
to the contlict waged, during its writing, in
the wounded psyche of Dickens. It is an epic,
marvelously courageous, struggle. Dickens fails
to repress, transmute, comprehend, control,
transcend the private impulses which are the
work's occasion. His great expectation, one
might say the great expectation of art generally,
is precisely this translation of private matter into
public discourse, the triumphant escape from
personality, from Yeats's "foul rag-and-bone
shop of the heart." No doubt, Vivian, in "The
Decay of Lying," is right: "The only real people
are the people who never existed.... To art's
subject-matter we should be more-or-less indifferent."
But few would give up Dickens for Wilde.
Nor need it surprise or distress us that we see and
can verbalize complexities in Great Expectations
when Dickens, who made us see, seems innocent
of our psychological sophistication. Dickens was,
as few have been, alert to and loyal to his own
feelings. We stand on Freud's shoulders. Freud
stood on Dickens'.31
Unilversityo f Toledo
Toledo, Ohio
Notes
' Quoted by Harry K. Girvetz. Beyon(d Rilht anid( Wronli. A
Sttud in Moral Theorr (New York: Free Press, 1973). p. 54.
from Letters of'Si,lutnd Freul, ed. Ernst L. Freud (New York:
Basic. 1969). p. 436.
Gi. K. Chesterton, ('riticisms ttnAd IIpprlechoit.i onsf ('arles
Dickens (New York: Dutton, 1911), p. 197: John H. Hagan,
Jr.. "The Poor Labyrinth: The Theme of Social Injustice in
Dickens's Great E.pectations.," Nineteenth-CenturvFl iction, 9
(Dec. 1954). 169--78; Monroe Engel, The Maturtity of Dickens
(Cambridge. Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 1959), pp. 156-68;
G. Robert Stange, "Expectations Well Lost: Dickens' Fable
for His Time." College English. 16 (Oct. 1954). 9.
3 Great Expectation.s, ed. Frederick Page, The New Oxford
Illustrated Dickens (London: Oxford Univ. Press. 1953). p.
434: Ch. Ivi. All subsequent reterences to this work are fiom
this edition and are noted by chapter and page number within
the text.
' Robert B. Partlow, Jr., "The Moving 1: A Study of the
Point of View in Great Expectations," Collhege English. 23
(Nov. 1961). 122 26. 131. discusses this difficult question. 5 See e.g.. Humphry House, Ilhe lDicken.s 1orl.ld 2nd ed.
(London: Oxford Univ. Press, 1942).
6 An important treatment of this subject is Julian Moynahan.
"The Hero's Guilt: The Case of Great E.pectations."
EssaYs in Criticism, 10 (1960), 60-79. Barbara Hardy disagrees
with vigor ("Formal Analysis and Common Sense." Essas:s
in Criticism. 11, 1961. 112--15) but Moynahan, writing in the
same issue, will not be moved ("Dickens Criticism." pp. 239
41). See also Robert Barnard, "Images and Theme in Great
Expectations..
" Dickens Stulies Annual. 1 (1970). 238-51
448
Lawlrence Jay Dessner
("The all-pervasive theme of Great Expectations is not money,
but guilt," p. 238), and Harry Stone, "Fire, Hand, and Gate:
Dickens' Great Expectations," Ken yon Review, 24 (1962),
662-91.
7 I follow David Goldknopf, The Life of the Novel (Chicago:
Univ. of Chicago Press, 1972), pp. 146-47, who quotes this
passage and refers to the "wink" in it.
8 Ne\w Republic, March 1940, pp. 297-300, 339-42. I quote
from the enlarged version in The Wound and The Bolt.: Seven
Studies in Literature (New York: Oxford Univ. Press, 1965),
pp. 3-85, and indicate future page references in my text.
Wilson's influence in this regard has been widespread. It
limits the often insightful Freudian reading of Albert Hutter's
"Crime and Fantasy in Great Expectations," in Psychoanalysis
and Literary Process, ed. Frederick Crews (Cambridge, Mass.:
Winthrop, 1970), pp. 26-65.
9 Holland, "Romeo's Dream and the Paradox of Literary
Realism," Literature and( Psycholoq,. 13 (1963), 97-104.
quotes and discusses this statemlent of Freud's. In his essential
work on the subject, The Dynamics of Literary Response (New
York: Oxford Univ. Press, 1968), Holland touches on the
linkage between sentimentality in popular fiction and "oedipal
fantasy" from which "most of the greatest literature...
builds" (pp. xiii-xiv, 47); Stoehr, Dickens. The Dreamer's
Stance (Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press, 1965); Stoehr's critical
method and his remarks on Great Expectations are most useful
although his conclusions about the novel's "true subject"
(p. 99) are at variance with mine.
'0 Sylvia Anthony's The Discovery of Death in Childhood
(New York: Basic, 1972) is a useful summary. Most volumes
of The Psychoanailtic Study of the Child (New York: International
Univs. Press) and of the Journal of Child Psycholoqy
andC Psychiatry contain relevant material.
l The Form of Victorian Fiction. Thackeray, Dickens,
Trollope, George Eliot, Meredith, and Hardy (Notre Dame:
Univ. of Notre Dame Press, 1968), p. 6.
12 Charles Klingerman, "The Dream of Charles Dickens,"
Journal of the American Psychoanalysis Association, 18 (1970),
784.
3 The Poetical Works of' Matthei- Arnold, ed. C. B. Tinker
and H. F. Lowry (London: Oxford Univ. Press, 1950), p. 193.
14 Charles Burkhart, Charlotte Bronti.: A Psychosexual
Study of Her Novels (London: Gollancz, 1973), p. 73.
5 "Thanatos: The Death Instinct in Dickens' Later
Novels," Psychoanalysis anc Psychoanalytic Review, 47
(Winter 1960--61), 28.
16 Dickens was interested in the relationship between his
dreams and his fiction, as Warrington Winters has shown
("Dickens and the Psychology of Dreams," PMLA, 63, 1948,
984-1006); Dickens was not the only Victorian who believed
that "there is a mental existence within us, a secret flow, an absent
mind which haunts us like a ghost or a dream and is an
essential part of our lives." So wrote Eneas Sweetland Dallas.
7he Gay1 Sc'ince (London: Chapman & Hall. 1866). . .199
(quoted by Helene E. Roberts, "The Dream World of Dante
Gabriel Rossetti," Victorian Studies, 17, 1974, 380). On the
limits of Dickens' awareness of depth psychology, see Leonard
F. Manheim. "The Personal History of David Copperfield: A
Study in Psychoanalytic Criticism1," Allm1 ricualon1 ,1 9
(1952), 21 43, esp. 41-43.
7 R. D. McMaster, ed., Great Expectations (New York:
Odyssey, 1965), p. 6, n. See also Charles Parish. "A Boy
Brought Up 'By Hand,' " Nineteenth-Century Fiction, 17
(1962), 286--88, and Robert J. Finkel, "Another Boy Brought
Up 'By Hand,'" Nineteenth-CenturyEF iction, 20 (1966),
389-90.
18 Manheim. "Personal History of David Copperfield," p.
42.
'1 "As kingfishers catch fire, dragonflies draw Ilamlc. I l
Poems of Gerard Manlei' Hopkins, ed. W. H. Gardner and
N. H. Mackenzie, 4th ed. (London: Oxford Univ. Press,
1970), p. 90.
20 See my "Great Expectations: The Tragic Comedy of John
Wemmick," Ariel. A Reviewl of International Enqlish Literature,
6 (April 1975), 65-80.
21 See Moynahan, "The Hero's Guilt," and Karl P. Wentersdorf,
"Mirror Images in Great E.pectations," Nineteenith-
Century Fiction, 21 (1966), 203-24.
22 Jay Leyda, ed., The Complete Stories of Herm7anM elville
(New York: Random, 1949), p. xxviii.
23 I follow J. Hillis Miller, Charles Dickens:. The World of.
His Novels (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univ. Press, 1958),
esp. pp. ix-xi.
24 "The Law as 'Father,'" A,merican /inuito, 12 (1955),
17 23.
25 See Manheim, "The Law as 'Father,'
"
p. 21, on Bleak
House: "There never was a kindlier, more long-suffering,
gentler father than John Jarndyce.... What better atonement
could one make to a once-despised father? [i.e., Dickens'
father]."
26 Bella Wilfer, Jenny Wren, Amy Dorrit, and their fathers,
to name a few.
27 Quoted by Roberts, p. 392, from "The Relation of the
Poet to Day-Dreaming," SigmmunFdr eud, Charaictera nd Culture,
ed. Philip Rieff (New York: Collier, 1963), p. 38.
28 Shirley Panken, The Joy of Sufferin.' The Psychoanalytic
Theory and Therapy of Masochism (New York: Aronson,
1973). Panken speaks of "Moral Masochism" (p. 41)
and says that "Masochistic individuals remain unaware of the
extent to which they fear and exaggerate moral failure" (p.
43).
29 The debate is summarized by K. J. Fielding, "The Critical
Autonomy of Great Expectations," Review of' EnIlish
Studies, 2 (1961), 83-85.
30 Graham Greene, "The Young Dickens," The Lost Childhood
rand Other Essays (London: Eyre & Spottiswoode, 195 1),
p. 54, paraphrases and then quotes from G. K. Chesterton,
Charles Dickens, a Critical Study (New York: Dodd, Mead,
1906), pp. 170-71, Ch. vii.
31 I acknowledge with gratitude the helpful counsel of my
colleagues, Louis B. Fraiberg and Wallace D. Martin, at the
Univ. of Toledo, and the incisive criticism and suggestions of
George H. Ford, James R. Kincaid, and William D. Schaefer.
449